symposium
Q: Do patents and copyrights undermine private property?
Yes:
They are a burden to marketplace transactions and discourage business
startups.
By Ilana Mercer and N. Stephan Kinsella
Property and liberty are
intricately linked. In fact property, not representative government or majority
rule, exemplifies freedom. Property is a sphere in which the individual can be
free of government; the historical role of private property as countervailing to
the power of the state cannot be overstated. Equally strong is the relationship
between strong private-property rights and prosperity. If nothing else, the
dismal economic failure of socialism has demonstrated what transpires when
private ownership of the means of production is abolished.
The insidious and persistent
encroachment on property by the modern welfare state has, however, resulted in a
complete confusion about the nature of ownership. By undermining the ethical
foundations upon which property rests, the welfare state has made it morally
acceptable to give people access to property they don’t own. Property grabs run
the gamut from taxation, welfare programs, forfeitures, and environmental and
antitrust legislation to the more subtle interference with freedom of contract
inherent in minimum-wage laws and affirmative hiring.
Copyright and patent grants of
privilege are another form of property infringement — courtesy of the state.
While they have their origins in a much earlier privilege given to “friends of
the crown,” in their modern incarnation they blend in with the welfare state’s
wealth-distributing impetus. Far from being “natural” property rights grounded
in the common law, patent and copyright are monopoly privileges granted solely
by state legislation.
Copyright
gives authors of original works (e.g., books) the exclusive rights to copy the
work or to prepare “derivative works” based on the original. A patent gives an
inventor the right to stop others from making, using or selling the patented
invention. In both cases, the holder of this right is given legal control over
how others use their property. As the author of a differently hued Gone with the
Wind recently found out, the copyright holder can stop you from using your own
paper and ink to publish a novel that reproduces the copyrighted work or one
based on its plot. The estate of Margaret Mitchell, author of Gone with the
Wind, is suing Alice Randall to block her from publishing the parody The Wind
Done Gone. Randall tells the famous tale from the perspective of black slaves.
The mere act of creation —
composing a song, penning a novel or inventing a mousetrap — gives the creator
control over the tangible property of others. In addition to allowing the author
partially to control the paper, ink, computer and photocopies of others,
copyright in particular restricts not only our rights to our property, but to
our very bodies. Consider the choreographer of a dance who gets the right to
stop another from moving his body in a certain fashion.
First Amendment rights to freedom
of speech also are compromised. A recent court order obtained by factions of the
entertainment industry decreed that source code (a computer program) is not
protected free speech, and the studios have a right to suppress it. What next?
Do we unleash the force of the law against a devotee who recites computer code
on a street corner?
It gets worse.
You don’t have to be guilty of copyright violation to be constrained; doing
something that might result in some third party making prohibited copies will
suffice. A particularly rank example of prior-restraint legislation is the Audio
Home Recording Act of 1992. Manufacturers of digital-recording devices are
compelled by law to incorporate technology that prevents copying; they are
penalized in anticipation of possible infractions. Manufacturers also are made
to pony up royalties in lieu of each device of blank media sold. Ditto for
consumers who pay through excise taxes.
Patents, however, take the cake.
The patent holder can prevent others from practicing invention even if, as is
quite common, they arrive at the process quite independently. Happen to think of
a new way to tune your car engine to get better gas mileage? Better hope someone
else does not have a patent on that technique; he could stop you from twiddling
with your own 1967 Mustang in your own garage.
Thinking of dashing off a quick
software-filing program to streamline your business? Think again.
“Software-driven, multihost storage solutions for powering advanced business
applications,” are being patented at a furious rate. Stripped of baffle gab,
this mouthful means that for the privilege of filing, albeit electronically, you
will have to pay extortion money to a patent holder. It gets scarier when you
consider that 20,000 software patents are issued annually.
Price-inflating patent monopolies
have grave consequences for undeveloped nations, as the latest patent imbroglio
unfurling in South Africa suggests. The government of South Africa enacted
legislation to allow parallel importing of, and domestic production of, generic
AIDS drugs to help deal with the AIDS crisis. The multinational pharmaceutical
kingpins moved in to enforce their patent monopolies, plunging South Africa into
a life-and-death battle.
South
African firms presumably have not stolen their equipment. Neither have they
trespassed or broken an entry to obtain the molecular combinations for AZT, 3TC
or ddI. These are in the public domain. So why should South Africans be
prohibited from making these drugs?
Given that it’s generally a bad
thing, through legislation, to transfer control of property from owner to
nonowner, what possibly is the justification for such laws?
Most proponents view intellectual
property (IP) as a matter of utility. Without such laws, the argument goes, we
would be deprived of clever inventions and beautiful works of art. To
utilitarians, the “costs” of monopoly privileges, not least the violation of
property rights, are outweighed by their benefits.
Utilitarians turn a blind eye to
the staggering sums companies spend on the fees of patent attorneys who prepare,
file and defend patent applications, mostly for defensive purposes. Litigation
costs millions. Mergers between companies often occur for no other reason than
to settle patent disputes or to allow the merging parties to compete with a
rival with a large patent armory. Submarine patents can emerge at any time, only
to sink a high-tech company. The threat of patents increases overall business
risk and can torpedo marginal or startup companies. If patents and copyright are
essential to innovation, as the mantra goes, how is it that day dawns and the
perfume maker who owns no odor-rights still is marketing high-end perfume that
can be knocked off? Philosophers persist in writing their tomes, mathematicians
toil at solving age-old riddles and physicists don’t tire from probing the
universe. How does all this creativity continue without the reward of a
monopolistic ownership in the ensuing ideas? And why is it fair for the law to
protect practical gizmos but not more abstract ideas such as Einstein’s equation
E=mc2?
So far, we’ve highlighted
how intellectual-property rights interfere with the freedom of others to use
their own bodies or their justly acquired property in certain ways. But why
should they not be accorded this right? Why should tangible goods be the proper
objects of property rights instead of intangibles such as the ideas IP laws
protect? Here we arrive at the nub of the issue.
“He who receives an idea from me,”
wrote Thomas Jefferson, himself an inventor, “receives instruction himself
without lessening mine; as he who lights his taper at mine, receives light
without darkening me.” Jefferson was very definitely not articulating the
fatuous “information-wants-to-be-free” argument made by the left regarding IP.
He was, however, enunciating what is the essence of ownable property.
Ownable property is only that
which is economically scarce. And by economic scarcity we mean that, absent
clear demarcation, conflict will arise as to who owns the resource. Land, cars,
printing presses, paper and ink are scarce in the sense that if we remove them
from you, you no longer have them. Our use of an item conflicts with your use of
it. While an abundance of computers can be had on the market, our use of this
particular personal computer excludes your use of it. If we could conjure
computers with a genie gesture, they would be abundant, not scarce, and it would
be immaterial if this one were removed.
However valuable, ideas are not
economically scarce: Our listening to a piece of music doesn’t conflict with or
exclude your doing the same. A copy made of a book doesn’t remove from its
author the configuration of ideas that is the book. Ideas, very plainly, can be
jointly consumed without dissipating.
Of course, the end product of an
idea — to wit, a book or a compact disc — is very definitely scarce. True to
John Locke, we say that if you purchase the book or buy the CD, you are its
rightful sole owner. Proponents of IP, however, say that some distant author or
musician partially may colonize your book and CD and tell you how to use them.
How do we allay the fear that
without patent and copyright we would all perish? Consider this: How many tears
would you shed if Bill Gates were worth only several — not dozens of —billions?
Since Microsoft owes a good portion of its wealth to the copyright monopoly,
this would be the upshot of its removal. If the company relied only on profits
from initial sales and from support services, would that be so bad?
Being “first on the market” is its
own reward. The various spin-offs and short-term advantages that accrue to
innovators who develop new products provide sufficient incentive and profit to
render patent protection unnecessary. Removal of patent protection often can
accelerate research-and-development efforts. No sooner had Eli Lilly been
stripped of its patent protection for Prozac than the company pledged a renewed
commitment to innovation. This was reflected in investor confidence and climbing
stock prices.
Innovators can and
do “fence” their products. As IP scholar Tom Palmer points out, concerts and
circuses are fenced-in events with “tickets sold and checked at the door.” There
already are assorted blank recording media on the market that scramble signals
beyond recognition, making reproduction impossible.
Bundling of products is a viable
option as are tie-ins: these arrangements wed a product to a service. Television
broadcasts already are tied to advertising, as are so many other goods. Computer
programs are bundled with manuals or service features. The customer would rather
purchase the product and get access to free maintenance than resort to copying.
Contracts, of course, inherently
are free-market friendly. Unlike IP rights, they are voluntary and bind only
parties to the agreement. There are leasing arrangements, too. Companies can
enforce their property rights in the end product of the idea, the tangible good.
They then lend the thing out subject to conditions specified in a contract.
Patent and copyright clearly
undermine private property. A staunch defense of private property must lead to
anti-intellectual-property conclusions.
[The views expressed in this
article are the personal opinions of the authors and should not be attributed to
any other entity.]
Mercer
is a free-lance editorial writer based in Seattle and writes on intellectual
property for the National Post and Ideas on Liberty. Kinsella has
written widely on patent law and is vice president specializing in intellectual
property at Applied Optoelectronics Inc. in Sugarland, Texas.
No: Ownership of ideas and a market system are
the only reliable incentives for productivity.
By James DeLong
A decade ago the topic of
intellectual property (IP) — patents on inventions; copyrights on books, music,
movies and software; trademarks on brand names; secrets such as formulas for
soft drinks — was a snoozing backwater of the law. Now it is hot! Cool! There!
The driving force behind the
obsession is simple: money. Financial markets are dependent on IP. In 1978, the
book value of tangible property owned by publicly traded companies equaled 83
percent of the value of these companies’ stocks and bonds. By 1998, this
tangible book value was only 31 percent of total value, meaning that 69 percent
of the total came from IP and good will. (Some of the market value actually came
from moonshine, but 1998 preceded the biggest inflation of the NASDAQ bubble.)
Concern about IP is magnified by
the Napster software for swapping music over the Internet. It demonstrates the
vulnerability of IP in the digital age and threatens to implode the recording
industry. Concern, perhaps panic, also is reinforced by ongoing lawsuits over
DeCSS, the software that decodes the encryption system that protects movies on
DVD disks. With DeCSS rocketing around the Internet, Hollywood fears the worth
of any movie put onto a DVD disk will be zero.
Consumers should fear this, too,
because it would mean no more movies on DVD, but they have not glommed on to
this part of the deal yet. Their current reaction to both DeCSS and Napster is:
“Hey! Free stuff.” The obsession with IP is triggering intense debates at both
the micro and the macro levels.
At
the micro level, the debate jumps around among many topics. Because we do not
let people copyright “facts,” such as sports scores or stock quotations, how do
we encourage investment in creation of useful databases? Is it legitimate to
allow patents on “business methods,” such as Amazon’s one-click method of
ordering? How do we treat information residing in the head of an employee who
leaves a firm — and should law distinguish between information acquired “on
company time” and a worker’s own creative idea?
There are issues of parodies and
book reviews and improvements on existing inventions and the doctrine of patent
equivalents and a zillion other nuts-and-bolts problems. If all creativity draws
on a huge “cultural commons,” as indeed it does, how do we decide how much
people should be allowed to fence off as their own?
At the macro level, discussion is
more fundamental: Should IP be recognized at all? Some analysts of a libertarian
bent reject the basic legitimacy of property rights in the products of the
intellect. To explain why I think they are wrong, it is useful to reprise the
thinking behind our recognition of the human right to own and use property.
Tough human institutions are like
tough trees: They have multiple roots and draw stability from the combination.
The idea of property is one of the toughest of human institutions, existing in
all cultures across the ages, so we would expect to find it supported by a dense
root system. A big root is the concept of Lockean justice. Ownership of one’s
own self and effort is the most basic of human rights. Since material things are
produced when people mix their labor with natural resources, the idea that one
owns the fruits of this effort is powerful.
Accompanying this concept of
justice is the pragmatic truth that ownership creates incentives for
productivity. People might garden for fun, or hunt, dig ditches or write
symphonies, but not much. Even if they wanted to, they would have to make a
living, which reduces time and energy available for creativity on the side.
Giving the producer a property
right in the output of his effort, or letting him earn pay in exchange for
producing it, is the only sure way to foster these activities, outside of
compulsion.
Property rights also
are important for efficient allocation of resources. If something is scarce, the
best way to ensure that it is put to its most productive use is to assign it to
an owner motivated to find this best use. Property rights are a keystone of a
complex market system that allocates resources among myriad investment and
production possibilities. If society declares that crops belong to the grower
but that petroleum belongs to all in common, it will produce too many crops and
no oil. If it denies economic returns to IP, it will invest too little in
creating it.
Political reasons
favor recognizing property. Democracy works best, and probably only, if citizens
are invested in the stability of the polity and have something to lose if its
politics run off the rails. Investment in the form of electronic bits or worker
know-how will serve as well as land or money.
And we have an interest in
promoting human autonomy. To the greatest extent possible, people should be free
to live their lives as they damn well please. It is impossible to imagine such
freedom except in the context of a society in which ownership of resources
liberates people from control by others. Again, intangible resources will do the
job as well as material ones.
All
these bases for endorsing the institution of property apply full force to the
concept of IP, except for one: the point about allocating scarce resources. A
pasture needs an owner. If it is a commons used by everyone, it soon will be
exhausted and the sheep will starve, followed by their owners.
IP is different because many
people can use it at once. You can play a song without interfering with my
playing of exactly the same song at the same time. Millions of others can join
us, each at his own device. This also is true of patents — you can copy the
design of my machine without taking it from me. We can all graze our sheep on
the same intellectual commons without exhausting it. Or, to paraphrase Thomas
Jefferson, you can light your candle from mine without taking my light.
This is indeed a powerful
difference between physical and intellectual property. It greatly influences
analysis of many knotty micro issues. But it does not justify total rejection of
intellectual property because the other roots remain.
Lockean justice still demands that
I own the product of my labor. We still need to give people incentives to
produce. We still need market signals that people should invest in producing
intellectual as well as physical capital, and we still need the level of the
returns to this investment to reflect at least roughly the rate of return to
society.
The health of democratic
government and the fostering of human autonomy are still served by intellectual
property as well as by physical property. Opponents of IP make some additional
arguments, but none are satisfactory. One is that creators can protect their
work by contract and do not need the support of property law. But intellectual
property must be disclosed to third parties who are not bound, and after that it
is loose in the world.
This
contention also assumes a perfectly functioning legal system and low transaction
costs. Neither is realistic. Besides, to say that a creator has the right to
limit disclosure seems to concede the central point — that he has a right of
some sort.
Opponents sometimes
argue that IP interferes with others’ abilities to use their physical
properties, as when your copyright on a book limits my use of my printing press.
But so what? Society constantly is resolving conflicts over uses of property,
and there is no reason to say that tangible property automatically trumps
intangible.
Finally, opponents say
creativity will find a way and that products of the mind still will be cranked
out even without ownership. This is partly true, but neither the quantity nor
the quality will approach that produced by property rights and a market system.
Patronage sometimes is cited as an
alternative, but to advocate reliance on the whims of billionaires and dukes or,
worse, the National Endowments or National Public Radio, is an odd position for
libertarians. Nor is sponsorship à la broadcast TV an answer. That industry does
not sell a product to consumers; instead, it sells eyeballs to advertisers, a
very different model that results in programming at the lowest common
denominator.
In “free” television,
the amount spent on a show for my viewing is limited to the profit a sponsor can
make from selling me a box of detergent, which probably is about 10 cents.
As a consumer, I am better off
with pay television. Then those of like mind can combine and offer to pay $2 or
$100 for a product that suits our tastes. It is no accident that The Sopranos, a
subtle and masterful work, is on pay TV. But this works only if the creator has
a mechanism for selling to me, which means a property right.
Napster partisans are in a
comparable situation. Intellectual-property opponents are correct in thinking
that music still will exist, even if it isn’t paid for. But it will be from a
few bands that can pack ’em in on a tour, plus 100,000 versions of the kazoo
group that rehearses in the garage on Saturday because they must hold down real
jobs during the week.
I prefer
Bruce Springsteen, the New York Philharmonic and a plethora of other
professional musicians who are paid so that those with the most talent are drawn
into the business and then freed to be devoted full time to music. And I will
fight those who, in the name of a misguided concept of liberty, would deny me my
right to pay them.
DeLong is a senior fellow in the Project on Technology &
Innovation at the Competitive Enterprise Institute in Washington. He also is the
author of Property Matters.