From my recent TLS post: Corporate Personhood, Limited Liability, and Double Taxation, LibertarianStandard.com (Oct. 18, 2011).
Also cross-posted at Mises; archived comments below.
Corporate Personhood, Limited Liability, and Double Taxation
by Stephan Kinsella on October 18, 2011 @ 2:56 pm · 0 comments
The politics of the left-oriented Occupy Wall Street (OWS) movement, like that of the right-oriented modern Tea Party movement, is not very well defined. But one of the things some of the OWS participants are calling for in their list of “demands” is an end to “corporate personhood.” In this they echo the views of left-libertarians who contend that state-chartered “corporations” are the source of grave social ills.
Some of these issues were recently debated on the pages of Roderick Long’s blog, in the comments to his post “Double Standard.” Left-libertarians who oppose incorporation, and usually also “capitalism,” argue that firms derive some great benefit from the state by the privilege of incorporation. The standard leftist critique of the corporation is the “concession” theory outlined by Robert Hessen in his seminal study In Defense of the Corporation (see a key excerpt from pp. 18-21). They argue that the state grants to corporations three features: entity status, perpetual duration, and limited liability to shareholders, all of which are artificial and would not exist absent state intervention. Left-libertarians maintain that these privileges grant corporations more power than they otherwise would have, which distorts the market, nay, society in general. This gives rise to more “hierarchy” and “authoritarianism” than would prevail in what Hans-Hermann Hoppe calls a private law society, and indeed, to “exploitation” of the workers by the bourgeoisie.
- October 18, 2011 at 7:41 pm
-
This is some tasty and strong stuff, brother.
- October 19, 2011 at 9:07 am
-
Kinsella: “The problem with this theory is the assumption that in a private law society, “shareholders” should be vicariously liable for the negligence of others.”
Let’s not use the word “shareholder.” Let’s call the stockholder what he is: the (or, an) owner. There is nothing vicarious about the damage caused by the (an) owner of anything, whether it be a dangerous pit bull or a dangerous corporation, such as a nuclear-power generating corporation.
Kinsella: “We have to recognize that the prima facie answer—the default condition—is no: each person is responsible only for his own torts, not for those of others. To hold someone else liable requires some kind of “vicarious liability” theory. ”
The pit bull can’t pay, so his owner is responsible. Same with the owners of corporations. No need for any “vicarious liability” theory because there is nothing vicarious about the relationship nor the liability of an owner for his pit bull or her corporation. There is no “vicarious liability” theory involved because there is no “someone else.” There is only the owner.
Kinsella: “But holding employers—or shareholders—vicariously liable for actions of their employees relies on the offensive, paternalistic, feudalistic concept of respondeat superior—a master is responsible for his slaves’ or servants’ transgressions. As Hessen notes, this is just a vestige of the medieval mentality. Why would a shareholder be liable for actions of some employee?”
What is offensive is this is that this statement is deceptive and utter nonsense. The agent-principal relationship is alive and well in law and in relationships recognized as such throughout the world. It is ancient, of course, but most truths are, and modern lawyers are as unable to refute them as were their medieval predecessors down through the ages. Why didn’t the author or Hessen use this modern, non-offensive, non-paternalistic, non-feudalistic term? And since you repeat the same unjustified assertions over and over, let me also be repetitive: We are not talking about a “stockholder” liability for “some employee,” what the author is talking about is an owner’s responsibility for his or her potentially dangerous property or operation. The author would incise the owner from his property, but the ownership of property (viz., private property) is crucial to every libertarian theory I have ever encountered.
Kinsella: “On the other hand…he may have bought the share from a previous shareholder. ”
This is a silly argument. Whether one bought the pit bull as a puppy or a trained fighting dog is immaterial to our owner’s relationship to the property.
Kinsella: ” They assume that giving money to the corporation is akin to “aiding and abetting it…”
This is a strawman, one of so many in this article that I can’t even begin to count them let alone address them all. For this one let me just say, no one need assume anything of the sort, and I doubt anyone so assumes. No owner (stockholder) of a business “gives” it money. An owner either creates the business by an initial investing, or buys it as a going concern. Obviously how ownership is obtained has no affect whatsoever on the pit bull’s behavior nor on whether or not the reactor core melts during a tsunami. Nor does this point have any place in a *rational* argument. Like the argument in total, it is a lawyer-like attempt to ameliorate if not eliminate the personal responsibility involved in human action upon which liberty utterly depends.
If I were to characterize the argument in this article, as it characterizes any imagined opposing view, the kindest thing I could say is that it is silly. Not only is personal responsibility compatible with libertarian theory, it is the ultimate foundation of liberty. The author’s attempt to relieve owners of responsibility for their pit bulls or their dangerous operations engaged in for profit is essentially an attack on individual liberty in the manner of a lawyer defending a losing cause with one frivolous argument piled upon another until the judge finally orders her to “shut up.”
I could pick the rest of the article apart straw man by indirect ad hominem aimed at whoever might have the temerity to oppose this sanctimonious view, but suffice to say again that the only “vicarious” relationship is a figment of a creative imagination. And if my counter to this diatribe should be characterized as left-libertarian, I would have to classify this article as pure statist, but that would be adopting the methodology of this author’s endeavor to oppose personal responsibility and the individual liberty resulting therefrom.
There are other good reasons why corporations, which are purely products of State legislation, are harmful to liberty not addressed by the article. One big one is the so-called “legal fiction,” which holds that corporations are “persons” for the purpose of standing in legal proceedings. As a direct result of this fiction, many court rulings (including those of the Supreme Court) have been made in cases wherein the parties were the State and a corporation which established important precedents, which precedents were later applied to cases involving the State and individuals as though the latter were equivalent to corporations and without the human rights that can only be claimed by individuals. An example of this is the famous case of Brushaber vs. Union Pacific Railroad (http://laws.lp.findlaw.com/getcase/us/240/1.html), in which SCOTUS declared that the newly enacted federal income tax did not violate the Constitution as claimed in that case and therefor Union Pacific must pay it. From then (1916) until the present, that case has been cited in lower federal courts as having determined that the income tax was constitutional. It has been cited as precedent to deflect thousands of cases of individuals who have tried to challenge the constitutionality of the income tax as applied by the IRS against them, even though Brushaber never even considered the constitutionality of the income tax as applied to real individuals who are not legal fictions created by State legislation.
The State and corporations are so intimately tied to one another that defending the latter is virtually defending the State and its illicit powers, without which no corporation has ever existed.
- October 19, 2011 at 10:41 am
-
Ownership of a pit-bull is more akin to owning a (potentially leaky, probably perfectly safe) propane tank than it is to partial ownership of a stockholding company. You yourself referred to the principal-agent relationship, the asymmetrical nature of which arises primarily because the latter commands faculties and resources unavailable to the former. This does not characterize an owner and his pet, which has (obviously) little by way of personhood but still generates liabilities for its owner. Tracing negligence from dog, which has no purposeful, rational action in the Misesian sense, to owner, who presumably does, is a trivial matter; establishing a causal relationship between (to use Kinsella’s example) the Pepsi driver and stockholders of Pepsi is not so trivial. This is not to suggest that liability is not, in some tenuous, circuitous manner, traceable, only that the claimant would encounter greater difficulty in trying. I can see a case being made for holding the employer responsible, and by extension, Pepsi Co., if the driver’s history or particulars about his habits are unearthed of which his superiors can credibly be shown to have been aware, or have overlooked. Perhaps the regional manager directed freighters to overload Pepsi fleet vehicles by an amount just above the optimal weight for safe braking distance. This seems actionable. However, this is a far cry from holding Pepsi’s boardmembers, and then stockholders, liable of same, beyond the diminished flow of rent by holding stock in a company now party to litigation. The relationship is there, but the existence of purposeful action on the stockholders’ part, bringing about an undesirable outcome, is not apparent.
Which cuts to the heart of my contention with this whole line of thinking. This seems to me more of a continuum problem, and more justifiably handled by the courts on an ad hoc basis rather than (as now exists) blanket immunity or (as Netterville suggests) enforcing total liability against all parties, regardless of participation. If the claimant can establish a causal relationship of purposeful action, bully for him; I doubt he can in any meaningful way, beyond the flow of capital and rent between the primarily responsible and the putative, peripheral parties. But I wouldn’t wish entirely to close off or open up the potential for liability.
The points you bring up regarding legal precedents are well taken, and I’ll read more about it—I’d love to see a response from Mr. Kinsella. Off the top of my head this seems moot if only because courts also find against individuals and thereby set unlibertarian precedents. The recent Angel Raich case comes to mind. A contentious issue like income tax, especially given the judicial activism surrounding its passage, would doubtlessly have found safe harbor in any number of cases. I’m not suggesting this particular case was not ultimately harmful, or that the modern conception of taxation does not turn on this decision, but merely that some court, somewhere, would doubtlessly have found in favor of the federal income tax, and that case would now serve as the precedent. Would the outcome have been materially different if textbooks instead referred to a conceivable case for the constitutionality of income tax withholding in which the court found against Vivien Kellems? I don’t know. We can’t say.
Thanks for the food for thought, both you and Mr. Kinsella. I am so novice about all of these concepts, I can really only bring up the untutored layman’s perspective and try clarifying my own position. I just wish the rhetoric weren’t so acerbic.
- October 19, 2011 at 5:41 pm
-
D. Storey, Thanks for engaging. See my reply to Wildberry below, which I think responds to you comment as well.
- October 19, 2011 at 11:20 am
-
Ned,
I can see this has gotten you fired up, but your understanding is a little shakey.Rarely have to rushed to the defense of Kinsella, but I think you are not deriving your criticisms from a correct understanding of the principles being discussed.
Shareholders are not employees, agents, or owners. They are shareholders, whose liabilities and powers are statutorily defined at the outset. Now you come along and want to change the nature of that in retrospect, not what the shareholder bargained for.
Your interpretation of vicarious liability is backwards, because the shareholders are neither employers or employees; they are investors whose proprtionality is a measure of share price.
A pit bull owner is liable for the tort of the Pit Bull, because it is the owner’s tort, negligence, which is at issue. The owner is not liable because of VL theory making the owner out to be the employer of the dog.
Also, an employee is not liable for the torts of the employer, and the employers is not liable for the torts of employees unless they are within the scope and course of their role as employee.
Shareholders are not “employers” precisely because they cannot exercise any control over the scope and course of the corporation, other than to vote and/or ratify materials acts of the BOD. They cannot ratify something that is illegal in the first place. The BOD controls the Executives adn the Executives control the employees. Shareholders buy in or sell off. That’s it.
I enjoyed your rant, but it would be helpful if you departed from some solid understanding of what you are criticising.
- October 19, 2011 at 2:48 pm
- October 19, 2011 at 6:15 pm
-
Wildberry, I’m sorry to have put you in a boat with Mr. Kinsella, which I know must be unconfortable–because, among other good reasons, his boat is about to sink even further when I respond to his silly, pit-bull rejoinder, in which he couldn’t resist attacking you as well. However to address your concerns directly:
“Shareholders are not employees, agents, or owners. They are shareholders, whose liabilities and powers are statutorily defined at the outset. Now you come along and want to change the nature of that in retrospect, not what the shareholder bargained for…Shareholders are not “employers” precisely because they cannot exercise any control over the scope and course of the corporation, other than to vote and/or ratify materials acts of the BOD. They cannot ratify something that is illegal in the first place. The BOD controls the Executives adn the Executives control the employees. Shareholders buy in or sell off. That’s it.”
Wild, you make my case. (As an aside, keep in mind, that the agent-principle relationship undoubtedly predates the state and human laws as does the ownership of private property. I believe both of these assertion can be deduced from the action axiom as Menger deduced that money predates the State, and, although I am neither an “economic anthropologist” nor an ethnologist, I doubt if there is any conflicting empirical evidence to the contrary.) The point is that before the State or in the absence of the State and its step child, the corporation, there was no such thing as a “stockholder.” There was the owner, responsible for his or her property. The corporation with its shareholder-owner, like the State itself, is a means of dispersing that all-important self-responsibility upon which liberty depends. Now if you’ll excuse me, I have to fit Mr. Kinsella with a new rectal orifice.
- October 19, 2011 at 1:05 pm
-
If I own a single $23 share of GM stock, the victim of a defective GM car should be able to seize my house? Nonsense.
D Storey makes an excellent point:
“Perhaps the regional manager directed freighters to overload Pepsi fleet vehicles by an amount just above the optimal weight for safe braking distance. This seems actionable.”In this case, the principal had direct control over the circumstances that resulted in injury. If the pit bull analogy has any weight at all, it is here. The pit bull owner has complete and direct responsibility for the dog at all times. If the dog injures someone, the owner is rightly held liable because of his negligence. The shareholder, however, has no direct involvement in the actions of employees, and therefore have no liability under this standard.
Aside from direct involvement, as I recall, the principal is only held liable when the agent injures someone while performing duties within his scope of employment, or if the agent was only able to injure another party because of the means supplied by the principal. I.E. a truck driver crashes a company vehicle while making a delivery, or a hotel employee robs a guest. In the first case, the driver was performing his duty (and using means supplied by the company), and in the second, the hotel provided the employee with access to the guest’s property. In both cases the principal is only liable because he supplied means that were misused or abused. This is where shareholders bear some liability, and it is entirely appropriate that this liability is limited to their contribution/stake in the firm. If a Pepsi driver gets drunk and crashes, the principal’s relationship to the injury is strictly commercial. The means that were supplied that occasioned the injury were strictly commercial. So, it’s entirely appropriate that, when the principal had no direct involvement in the injury, that his liability be limited to his contribution to the injury. Strictly speaking, you might say the liability is limited to the truck itself, but since the entire commercial operation is interdependent, it’s appropriate to expand liability to the entire commercial operation. It is not appropriate, however, to expand liability to the personal property of the principal when that personal property was not involved in or tied to any property that was involved in the jury.
To what extent should shareholders be liable when they have no direct involvement in the tort? The extent that they supplied means to facilitate the injury, which is their stake in the company.
- October 19, 2011 at 2:43 pm
- October 19, 2011 at 12:57 pm
-
I own a little over a share of Wal-Mart stock (big investor that I am!) and yet I have no control over Wal-Mart property, employees, or policy (or I should say, no more control than any other customer can exert). Why should I be out more than the value of my share if Wal-Mart executives or employees do something wrong or objectionable?
- October 19, 2011 at 1:12 pm
-
Likewise, why should you be held liable if you hire a trader to make investments on your behalf, and she buys a single share of Wal-Mart stock without your knowledge.
Likewise, why should you be held liable if you work for a company that offers a pension that includes stock in Wal-Mart, but you have no direct involvement in the investment decisions being made on your behalf, other than your continued willingness to work for your present employer.
- October 19, 2011 at 1:06 pm
-
The heretofore analysis has been narrowly confined to tort exposure.
Is there any consideration of shareholder gains that directly result from fraudulent corporate activity? E.g., Distillery XXX has been selling watered down booze and paying handsome dividends as a result. Are the shareholders’ earnings available to pay claimants in a class action suit brought by defrauded customers? Is the decline in price of Distillery XXX shares as a result of the de-capitalization of the corporation due to settlement payments just recompense for shareholders’ fraudulent gains?
This seems to be the area where “liability” is most murky. Is the concept of “fraudulent conveyance” applicable, or are shareholders shielded from such exposure?
- October 19, 2011 at 4:48 pm
-
Crickets. . . . ?!
- October 19, 2011 at 5:59 pm
-
@jasontgordon October 19, 2011 at 1:06 pm
Would you hold the investors that Bernie Madoff swindled liable for his fraud?
Fraud woud apply to them only if they knew Bernie was a crook and relied on that knowledge in making their decision to invest.
Those that lost money don’t have to pay a penalty to others who also lost money. But those that did make money might have to disgorge their profits which may be used to pay restitution to those who lost, but not because they are liable in the way you are thinking of it, but becasue they were unjustly enriched by the fraudulent conduct of Madoff.
Liability is murky where the facts are murky. But for fraud to apply, someone has to knowingly deceive someone for the purpose of getting some of their stuff. Shareholders are not fraudulent by accepting dividends that as far as they know, are legitimate.
- October 19, 2011 at 9:57 pm
-
not because they are liable in the way you are thinking of it
I don’t have a clue how or what you presume to be my thinking regarding investors, am I not clearly referring to shareholders?
So according to you Wildberry, dividends based upon fraudulent profits are justifiably owned so long as the shareholder accepted them in good faith? Give me a break. That logic would be convenient for a buyer of stolen goods, would it not?
Are shareholders in an actionable position to obtain damages related to their being payed dividends obtained fraudulently?
{ 26 comments… read them below or add one }