Podcast (kinsella-on-liberty): Play in new window | Download (40.3MB)
Kinsella on Liberty Podcast: Episode 439.
My appearance on The Rational Egoist: Debating the Moral Status of Intellectual Property with Stephan Kinsella: Part IIa. (Spotify) Michael will release the second half, PartIIb, later.
Shownotes:
The Rational Egoist: Resuming the Intellectual Property Debate with Stephan Kinsella (Part 1 of 2)
In this episode of The Rational Egoist, host Michael Liebowitz resumes his debate with Stephan Kinsella, a libertarian patent attorney and author, on the contentious issue of intellectual property. Picking up from their conversation a couple of weeks ago, Michael and Kinsella dive even deeper into the philosophical and legal arguments concerning IP rights. This is part one of a two-part series that explores the impact of intellectual property on innovation, individual rights, and economic systems. Join them for a rigorous exchange of ideas that challenges conventional thinking and sets the stage for the next episode’s continuation.
Michael Leibowitz, host of The Rational Egoist podcast, is a philosopher and political activist who draws inspiration from Ayn Rand’s philosophy, advocating for reason, rational self-interest, and individualism. His journey from a 25-year prison sentence to a prominent voice in the libertarian and Objectivist communities highlights the transformative impact of embracing these principles. Leibowitz actively participates in political debates and produces content aimed at promoting individual rights and freedoms. He is the co-author of “Down the Rabbit Hole: How the Culture of Correction Encourages Crime” and “View from a Cage: From Convict to Crusader for Liberty,” which explore societal issues and his personal evolution through Rand’s teachings.
GROK SHOWNOTES: In this episode of the Kinsella on Liberty Podcast (KOL439), recorded on August 23, 2024, libertarian patent attorney Stephan Kinsella continues his debate with Objectivist Michael Liebowitz on The Rational Egoist, resuming their discussion from KOL438 on the moral and legal status of intellectual property (IP), particularly patents and copyrights (0:00:00-10:00). Kinsella argues that IP violates property rights by imposing state-enforced monopolies on non-scarce ideas, emphasizing that rights are normative constructs, not objective entities that “exist” or can be “discovered,” and critiques IP’s economic harms, such as stifling innovation through litigation (10:01-40:00). Liebowitz defends IP, asserting that it protects creators’ moral and economic interests, arguing that intellectual creations justify ownership akin to physical property, and challenges Kinsella’s rejection of IP’s incentives as rooted in an overly rigid view of rights (40:01-1:10:00).
GROK DETAILED SHOW NOTES:
-
0:00:00-7:00 (Introduction and Recap, ~7 minutes)
Description: Host Michael Malice opens the debate, recapping the prior discussion (KOL438) and framing this as Part IIa of the IP debate between Kinsella’s libertarianism and Liebowitz’s Objectivism (0:00:00-0:02:00). Kinsella begins by reiterating his anti-IP stance, arguing that patents and copyrights violate property rights by monopolizing non-scarce ideas, and briefly notes that rights are normative constructs, not entities that “exist” or can be “discovered,” grounding his view in Austrian economics (0:02:01-0:04:30). Liebowitz restates his defense of IP, asserting that it morally and economically protects creators’ intellectual efforts, aligning with Ayn Rand’s philosophy of objective rights (0:04:31-0:07:00). The tone is civil, resuming the philosophical divide.
Key Themes:-
Recap of prior IP debate and introduction of Part IIa (0:00:00-0:02:00).
-
Kinsella’s anti-IP stance, emphasizing rights as normative, not discoverable (0:02:01-0:04:30).
-
Liebowitz’s Objectivist defense of IP as a creator’s right (0:04:31-0:07:00).
Summary: Malice sets the stage for the continued IP debate, with Kinsella critiquing IP as a violation of property rights and noting rights are constructed, while Liebowitz defends IP’s moral basis, establishing the core conflict.
-
-
7:01-22:00 (Philosophical Foundations: Rights and Scarcity, ~15 minutes)
Description: Kinsella elaborates that IP restricts non-scarce ideas, violating property rights over tangible resources, and explicitly states that rights do not “exist” as objective entities but are man-made normative concepts to resolve conflicts over scarce resources, challenging Liebowitz’s view (7:01-12:00). Liebowitz argues that IP is a legitimate extension of property rights, protecting the creator’s intellectual labor, and contends that rights are objective, discoverable through reason, per Rand’s philosophy (12:01-17:00). Kinsella responds that IP creates artificial scarcity, contradicting the non-aggression principle (NAP), and reiterates that rights are constructed tools, not “discovered” entities, using examples like a patented device to illustrate restrictions on physical property (17:01-22:00). The exchange is rigorous, with deep philosophical differences.
Key Themes:-
Kinsella’s view that IP violates property rights and rights are normative constructs (7:01-12:00).
-
Liebowitz’s defense of IP as protecting labor and rights as discoverable (12:01-17:00).
-
Kinsella’s critique of artificial scarcity and rights as non-discoverable (17:01-22:00).
Summary: Kinsella argues IP’s philosophical illegitimacy, emphasizing that rights are man-made, not discovered, while Liebowitz defends IP as a moral right, highlighting a libertarian-Objectivist divide.
-
-
22:01-37:00 (Economic Impacts: Innovation and Free-Riding, ~15 minutes)
Description: Kinsella critiques IP’s economic harms, citing studies (e.g., Boldrin and Levine, 2013) showing no clear innovation benefits and billions in litigation costs, arguing that IP stifles competition, particularly in tech and pharmaceuticals (22:01-27:00). Liebowitz counters that IP prevents free-riding, ensuring creators profit, and cites industries like film and music where IP supports economic viability, arguing that innovation thrives under IP regimes (27:01-32:00). Kinsella responds that market mechanisms, like first-mover advantages, incentivize innovation without IP’s coercive monopolies, and notes that rights are normative tools for justice, not entities “discovered” to justify IP’s existence (32:01-37:00). The debate is intense, with economic evidence central.
Key Themes:-
Kinsella’s critique of IP’s economic harms and lack of innovation benefits (22:01-27:00).
-
Liebowitz’s defense of IP as preventing free-riding and supporting innovation (27:01-32:00).
-
Kinsella’s market incentives argument and view of rights as constructed (32:01-37:00).
Summary: Kinsella highlights IP’s economic costs and advocates market alternatives, reinforcing that rights are man-made, while Liebowitz defends IP’s necessity, underscoring their economic and philosophical divide.
-
-
37:01-52:00 (Moral and Utilitarian Arguments for IP, ~15 minutes)
Description: Liebowitz emphasizes IP’s moral basis, arguing that creators deserve ownership of their intellectual efforts, and its utilitarian role in preventing underinvestment, aligning with Rand’s objective ethics (37:01-42:00). Kinsella refutes this, citing empirical studies (e.g., Machlup, 1958) showing inconclusive innovation benefits, and argues that IP’s state-backed monopolies violate the NAP, stating that rights are normative constructs, not “existing” entities to be discovered, challenging Liebowitz’s moral framework (42:01-47:00). Liebowitz accuses Kinsella of ignoring practical realities, like the need for IP in publishing, while Kinsella uses analogies (e.g., a recipe vs. a car) to clarify IP’s artificial restrictions (47:01-52:00). The exchange is heated, with philosophical tensions evident.
Key Themes:-
Liebowitz’s moral and utilitarian defense of IP to reward creators (37:01-42:00).
-
Kinsella’s empirical rebuttal and view of rights as normative, not discoverable (42:01-47:00).
-
Liebowitz’s practical concerns vs. Kinsella’s principled analogies (47:01-52:00).
Summary: Liebowitz defends IP’s moral and utilitarian necessity, while Kinsella counters with empirical evidence and the view that rights are constructed, highlighting a divide between pragmatism and libertarian principles.
-
-
52:01-1:07:00 (Market Alternatives and Objectivist Ethics, ~15 minutes)
Description: Kinsella argues that market alternatives, like open-source software and branding, outperform IP in fostering innovation, citing Linux, and reiterates that rights are man-made tools, not objective entities “discovered” in nature, challenging Liebowitz’s Objectivist ethics (52:01-57:00). Liebowitz counters that open-source is an exception, insisting IP is critical for industries like pharmaceuticals, where high costs require profit guarantees, and defends Rand’s view of rights as discoverable through reason (57:01-1:02:00). Kinsella challenges Liebowitz’s reliance on state coercion, arguing that IP contradicts free market principles, while Liebowitz accuses Kinsella of utopianism, emphasizing practical needs (1:02:01-1:07:00). The debate remains intense, with philosophical differences clear.
Key Themes:-
Kinsella’s defense of market alternatives and rights as constructed (52:01-57:00).
-
Liebowitz’s insistence on IP’s necessity and discoverable rights (57:01-1:02:00).
-
Kinsella’s critique of state coercion vs. Liebowitz’s practical defense (1:02:01-1:07:00).
Summary: Kinsella advocates market-driven innovation and views rights as man-made, while Liebowitz defends IP and discoverable rights, underscoring libertarian versus Objectivist perspectives.
-
-
1:07:01-1:22:00 (Q&A: IP’s Economic Impacts and Rights’ Nature, ~15 minutes)
Description: The Q&A begins, with an audience member asking about IP’s economic impact, prompting Kinsella to cite studies showing IP’s high costs and minimal innovation benefits, arguing that markets incentivize creativity without coercion, and emphasizing that rights are normative, not “existing” entities to be discovered (1:07:01-1:12:00). Liebowitz responds that IP’s absence would lead to underinvestment in creative sectors, citing pharmaceuticals, and defends rights as objective, discoverable entities per Rand’s philosophy (1:12:01-1:17:00). Another question on rights’ philosophical basis leads Kinsella to stress first-use principles, while Liebowitz defends creation-based rights, accusing Kinsella of ignoring practical outcomes (1:17:01-1:22:00). The Q&A highlights the philosophical divide.
Key Themes:-
Kinsella’s critique of IP’s costs and view of rights as normative (1:07:01-1:12:00).
-
Liebowitz’s defense of IP’s economic role and objective, discoverable rights (1:12:01-1:17:00).
-
Philosophical divide on rights: first-use vs. creation-based (1:17:01-1:22:00).
Summary: Kinsella defends market alternatives and constructed rights, while Liebowitz emphasizes IP’s necessity and objective, discoverable rights, reinforcing the debate’s core tensions.
-
-
1:22:01-1:37:00 (Q&A Continued: Practical Implications and Philosophical Divide, ~15 minutes)
Description: An audience question on IP’s practical implications prompts Kinsella to highlight open-source successes and IP’s litigation burdens, arguing that market competition drives innovation, and reiterating that rights are man-made, not “discovered” in nature, challenging Liebowitz’s framework (1:22:01-1:27:00). Liebowitz counters that IP is essential for competitive industries, preventing free-riding, and defends Rand’s view of rights as grounded in objective reality, accusing Kinsella of utopianism (1:27:01-1:32:00). Kinsella challenges Liebowitz’s state reliance, emphasizing the NAP’s principled stance, while Liebowitz insists on pragmatic governance to support IP (1:32:01-1:37:00). The Q&A underscores the ongoing divide.
Key Themes:-
Kinsella’s open-source examples and view of rights as constructed (1:22:01-1:27:00).
-
Liebowitz’s defense of IP’s practical necessity and objective, discoverable rights (1:27:01-1:32:00).
-
Kinsella’s NAP focus vs. Liebowitz’s pragmatic state defense (1:32:01-1:37:00).
Summary: Kinsella critiques IP’s burdens and defends constructed rights, while Liebowitz emphasizes IP’s practical role and objective rights, highlighting libertarian versus Objectivist views.
-
-
1:37:01-2:00:55 (Conclusion and Final Q&A, ~24 minutes)
Description: Kinsella concludes, urging rejection of IP as a violation of property rights and state coercion, directing listeners to c4sif.org for resources like Against Intellectual Property, and reiterating that rights are normative constructs, not entities to be “discovered” (1:37:01-1:40:00). Liebowitz makes a final defense, arguing IP’s necessity for innovation and moral recognition of creators, defending rights as objective and discoverable, and accusing Kinsella of ignoring economic realities (1:40:01-1:43:00). A final audience question on IP enforcement prompts Kinsella to emphasize market alternatives like branding, while Liebowitz defends state-backed IP to prevent free-riding (1:43:01-1:50:00). Malice ends the debate, with both acknowledging its depth, leaving little common ground, followed by a brief discussion on future topics (1:50:01-2:00:55).Key Themes:
-
Kinsella’s call to reject IP and state coercion, with rights as normative (1:37:01-1:40:00).
-
Liebowitz’s defense of IP’s economic and moral necessity, with objective rights (1:40:01-1:43:00).
-
Final Q&A on IP enforcement, highlighting libertarian-Objectivist divide, and future plans (1:43:01-2:00:55).
Summary: Kinsella concludes by advocating IP abolition and constructed rights, while Liebowitz defends IP’s pragmatic and moral role with objective rights, with the final Q&A and closing remarks underscoring their philosophical divide.
-
YOUTUBE Transcript
welcome to the rational egoist I’m your host Michael libowitz back with us today is Stefan canella he’s a patent attorney
and he’s also a prominent libertarian who’s been writing on issues of Liberty
for quite a long time Stefan welcome back to the show thanks so last time
Stefan was here we were talking about intellectual property and we were laying the foundations for the discussion um
we’ll begin today with we’ll do that a little bit to clear the foundations and then we’ll get into the IP stuff so
Stefan one thing two things and I I’ll get your take on both of them the the
first thing is you said that property rights are not the right to use but the
right to exclude and you also said that we have no right in things that are created only things that are discovered
or or homesteaded is that accurate well you have a right in things that are
created but the right doesn’t come from the fact of creation it comes from um
homesteading or contract okay um and and and you don’t have in general a right to
something that’s created you have a right to ownership of scarce resources
um which are things that there can be conflict over the way you determine who owns these resources is by um it’s by
homesteading or original appropriation and by Contra contract it so the Act of
Creation is not why you own a thing and
in fact the thing I think is proper to say the thing is not created nothing is created in terms of matter in the
universe even IR ran recognizes this um we just rearrange these things so when we talk about creation or production
which is more of an economic concept we have to be clear about what we mean I think that what we mean is we when we
produce things we produce wealth or we we produce things of value by
rearranging things that we already own so that’s why I try to keep those things uh separate and distinct okay so my
first question is why in your view is are property rights the right to
exclude and not the right to use and what would even be the difference so you can word it the normal
way but then you get tangled up uh and it’s less clear so you could say that owner owning a so owning a thing so
property rights are rights in resources over which there can be conflict so the
whole purpose of property rights is to assign an owner of the thing so that Outsiders know to avoid using those
things without the permission of the owner um so that’s what ownership rights are for but then the question is what’s
the nature of an ownership right um I I think it’s essentially a right to exclude and the and the way you can see
this is because owning a thing doesn’t give you the right to do anything you want with it now that is the common
objectivist or libertarian way of phrasing it you say that if you own your life or your body or other things you
can do whatever you want with these things as long as you don’t hurt other people um so they sort of build into
this right to use a limitation and the limitation is uh as long as you don’t
hurt other people um but that’s a little confusing in my view
because what’s really being limited by this prohibition against hurting other people is your actions because you know
you can harm someone with your actions alone even if you don’t use an owned
resource or if you use a resource that you don’t you don’t own like if I steal a gun or a knife from you and I use it
to shoot someone else the action that I’m performing is causing the uh
Invasion of the Body of someone else that they own contrary to their property right so
uh so owning a thing doesn’t mean you have to do whatever you want with it you can do whatever you want with it as long
as you’re not violating other people’s rights so then your permission is defined by other people’s property
rights which is ultimately what property rights are their rights to exclude so if someone else owns their body the reason
I can’t shoot them with with a gun or with a bullet from my gun is because
they own their body right so likewise my right to own
my so so their their right right to own their body is their their right to exclude to prevent you from using their
body without their permission they also have the right to allow you to use their body with their permission to give
permission to be shot or to be harmed right or to be like if if they give permission to a surgeon to to perform
surgery they’re consenting to the surgeon doing something with their body that the surgeon otherwise wouldn’t have
the right to do because the owner of that body has the right to exclude so that’s what I think um uh property
rights are it’s the right to exclude by the way this is this is the nature of patent rights
which we’ll get to shortly which is a type of IP right most people don’t understand this because it’s sort of technical jargon or Arcane but a patent
is the is not the right to to perform or practice an invention it’s the right to
stop other people from doing it so for example it’s the right to exclude um and
that’s because that’s what the nature of property rights are it’s the right to to prevent or to exclude people for example
if I obtain a patent from the government which I think is illegitimate as we’ll get to but let’s say the government
grants me a patent on a um on a three-legged stool okay like I’m the first guy that
invents the idea of a stool which is basically a stool would be a a seat a
seat member functionally attached to three leg members right for someone to
sit on so I would have a patent on that which means I would be able to prevent
people from making a stool from selling making or using or importing a stool now
let’s suppose someone else says hey if I add a back to this stool and maybe add four legs for more stability then this
stool becomes what I call a chair and I could get a patent on that which we would call it Improvement and the patent
would cover um a seating device having a seat four legs and a back member now
that could also be patented because it’s it’s different than the than the stool
however every element of the patent claims for the stool would be infringed by the by the chair because the stool
patent simply says a seat connected to three legs but a chair has a seat and it
has three legs so that means that the guy that invents the stool could get a patent on it but he couldn’t make a he
couldn’t make the chair I’m sorry the guy that gets a patent on the chair could not make the chair because that
would infringe the patent on the stool okay so so his right he could stop stop the stool maker from making an improved
stool with a with a with a back on it because he has a patent on that so the right for the stool patent owner to make
a stool would not mean he could improve his stool because that would be blocked by the other patent but the guy that
owns that patent couldn’t make the uh chair without infringing the stool patent so typically what they would do
is they would cross license with each other and they would both give each other permission to um so the stool
maker would the stool p owner would would would allow the chair maker to make his chair which would include
effectively a stool built into it and and usually vice versa but the point is
um if you say property rights are the right to use a resource then you’re stuck with saying well but but except
you can’t use it to hurt someone else’s property rights so then that looks like a limitation on property rights which
then people will seize on to say Well canella it you say that the problem with
IP rights is that it limits your ability to use your resource like your your
factory but all rights all property rights are limited because all property rights really are limits on other
people’s property rights so that’s the problem with that way of looking at it if you simply say property rights are
the right to exclude then I own a home or I own a factory and I don’t have the
right to use it in any way I want because I can’t use it to hurl rockets at your property or to or to take a gun
that I own and shoot you without your permission because your property rights prevent limit what actions I can perform
so if you simply look at property rights as the right to exclude people then the
fact that um the fact that your rights in your body prevents me from using my
gun the way I see fit it’s not a limitation on my property rights in my gun it’s just a limitation on my actions
um so that’s the reason I think we should look at it that way in the end it doesn’t matter too much because you could word it the typical libertarian
way and you could say that everyone has a property right in resources they they acquire justly and this gives them the
right to use it but then you have to add the caveat so long as they don’t use it to to invade the bordage of other
people’s property so let me just give you an an analogy that’s probably pretty
close I look at rights as basically this in ethics uh I don’t have the right to
initiate Force against somebody so I look at rights in a in a sense is in
what situation would I have the right to use force and it would be in defense so
to say I have a right to do something is similar to saying that I would have a right to use Force if somebody tried to
prevent me to do this I totally agree I think that’s ultimately what rights are rights are a statement about the
permissibility of the use of force when the recipient of that Force facially
objects to it right so it can either be put as I have the right to use speech I have the right
to go you know walk to the store whatever but it’s the flip side is it’s
it means that if somebody tries to stop me physically I have the right to retaliate and it seems like it’s the a
similar Dynamic is at play here where the traditional formulation of I have the right to do whatever I want as long
as I don’t violate the rights of others is the same same thing is saying I have the right to exclude others from doing
this I agree with all that uh but the way I’ve thought about it over the years um I I no longer believe that the right
to be free from the initiation of force is primary I think that’s more of a shorthand description of more
fundamental property rights um they imply each other so for example if you
say um you I have the right to my body to own my body I’m a self-
owner that is the same thing is saying uh it’s it unjust for you to
commit aggression because aggression means using my body without my permit without my permission but if if you’re
not permitted to use my body without permission that’s only because I own my body so there are different ways of saying the same thing ownership of my
body is the same thing as saying aggression is unjustified the problem is the word aggression if you just look at
it you know the way the word sounds and the meaning of it it really means physical fighting which implies physical
clashing between people’s body but the problem is we we expand the concept of
Rights um in our bodies which implies again aggression is not justified we
expand that concept of ownership of our bodies to other things that we own like like like real property and and movable
property like cars and food and homes and land um and when you say and this is
the pro so randians objectivists and Libertarians would say that well if you if you use someone’s someone’s home or
their or their car without their permission it’s a type of stealing or a type of trespass and then they call that
well that’s an that’s also an initiation of force or that’s aggression but it really doesn’t look like aggression
because it’s not aimed at someone’s body so the way I look at it is self- ownership is the Prototype body
ownership is the Prototype of ownership of other types of things and we do call
the invasion of self- ownership aggression but it’s sort of uh only by analogy or a stretch to say to extend
that that term that concept of aggression and say okay if I step on if I walk on someone’s lawn at midnight
when they’re not even awake and I to Reeve to retrieve uh you know my my my
football um I’m committing trespass against this person and we call that
aggression but what we really mean is it’s the unconsented to use of someone’s resources that they own so I think
that’s another reason to be careful about that word aggression um and again
I think that the only way to identify when something is aggression except in the in the in the simple case like me
hitting your body which where we assume each one owns their bodies right um for
anything else like if you’re if if I see two people fighting over a
wallet uh I don’t know who’s committing aggression because I don’t know who owns the wallet we need to know who owns the
thing to determine when there’s aggression so if it looks like one person is beating another person and
they’re committing aggression but what they’re really doing is using Justified Force to defend themselves or to
retrieve their stolen resource then it’s not aggression so we can only determine
whether an an apparent Act of aggression or an apparent Act of trespass or theft
we can only determine if it’s really theft or trespass once we determine who owns the thing in in dispute and we can
only determine that again by a very to the fundamental rights the fundamental rules of resource ownership which is
original appropriation and contract in a sense those are the only two rules of of property acquisition outside one’s own
body okay it’s it’s it’s original appropriation and contract so it sounds like you take the the rothbardian
perspective which I I disagree on some points I don’t want to debate about it because we got to get into other things
but I just want to get make clear is that rothbart held that all rights are property rights including your right to
your your body that that’s a a property right or self ownership that’s what that’s the position that you’re coming
from and I take that VI and I think by the way that’s compatible with aspects of Ran’s thought because on ran said
that we’re not ghosts we’re M material physical beings which is a recognition
that and and she also said that you know in G speech do you hear me there’s one
thing no one may do you may not use physical Force she used the word physical she recognized that
in the end and all Libertarians recognize this in the end all rights violations arise because of physical
conflict between people and the use of violence and violence can is a physical action that
can only be applied in the real world by the actions and motions of of an acting
human body against the against other physical things that can receive um
Force um so you could imagine some kind of right to your reputation or your
right to your soul but these are ghostly abstract things that don’t really exist
in a physical way so all rights are property rights because all rights can
be enforced and again the word in and this is compatible with objectivism enforceability means
physical Force so if you have the right to the Integrity of your home or your
body that means you have the right to use physical Force to repel an Invader
okay and Invader can only use physical Force to harm you if they just shout at you it’s just like je Jefferson in free
speech you know sticks and stones may break my bones but words cannot hurt me if someone just has an opinion about you
and says things they’re not invading the physical Integrity of your body this is why all property rights have to be um
All rights are property rights and all property rights are rights to control or
to exclude the use of scarce resources so yeah that is my view and I think it’s compatible with objective doesn’t by the
way so you’ve said you know multiple times you made the reference to man is
not a ghost that that certainly is from IR Randon you said that uh right is right to the physical Integrity of your
your property and the only rights violations are physical aggression physical
assaults that that sort of thing but to me that negates the you’re right that ran says
we are not ghosts but she also says we are not just merely physical bodies that we’re
integration there’s no mindbody dichotomy so the source of rights the
reason human beings ultimately have rights is because of our conceptual rational faculty because we have to
choose how to live we don’t come with a a pre-programmed Instinct on how to
survive we have to choose we have to think and that’s a function of our minds and I mean to to demonstrate that is
fairly simple I mean there’s a reason that crows don’t have rights or
chimpanzees don’t have rights and I mean I know the animals rights people may oh yes they do but they certainly don’t
have rights to property in the sense that human beings do and the the the reason is because the base of Rights the
foundation of Rights is the human consciousness it’s how we it’s it’s the
fact that we have to think we have to choose in order to survive I don’t strong disagree with that I do think
you’re sort of and of course this is compatible with li objectivism you’re blending together ethics and politics um
from an ethical point of view or a moral point of view as ran pointed out and I agree with her on this U the the purpose
of morals or ethics is to give uh acting human beings who have a complex
Consciousness and we have values um to give us a code a guide to
action to to know what is wrong and right to do that’s got nothing to do with with rights and interpersonal
things on on a first level because even cruso alone on his Island would have
some barebones morality attached to his actions if he wanted to live right if he wanted to live as a moral person and
live a good life within the constraint constraints of living without society and on its Island you know you could
still say the virtues like Thrift and oh absolutely I all apply to him and you could even say if he commits suicide not
maybe not suicide is being immoral because as Rand said a that’s a premoral choice although I would disagree with
her on that but um but yeah if he’s lazy and and he has a horrible month because
he didn’t save up you know catch enough fish that’s you could say it’s immoral because it’s not what he ought to be
doing to further his own life and to flourish within that context but when Society comes about and there’s other
people then the the domain of Ethics becomes even richer and there’s interpersonal ethics yeah again not even
rights related just whether it’s moral or moral or moral to treat other people certain ways to Value them to view them
in terms of Justice all this and then a subset of all that type of morality
would be rights and rights are like so I would say that that uh uh morals are are
or optional in the sense that um they’re up to the person to decide whether to
adopt or not you could say someone’s immoral they don’t but they have the they have the they have the choice to
choose to be lazy and to even be rude to other people but what they don’t have the right to do is to violate other
people’s rights those are the things that are must not shoulds okay so that’s how I view rights within that framework
but still I think that’s compatible with what I said earlier rights are property rights okay so just a minute or so ago
you said rights have nothing to do with morality well what I what what I what I
meant was um what I meant was uh yeah I wouldn’t say have nothing to do with it you could you can
view you are permitted it is arguable that there is a moral aspect to rights
but I do think they’re logically that they’re separate and here’s the reason why um I I said earlier in shorthand I
said that rights are a subset of morals I actually think that’s incorrect um most Libertarians would say
that everything that’s a rights violation is immoral but not everything that’s immoral is a rights violation
right so they view they view rights violations as a proper subset of morality yeah um but that implies that
rights are a subset of morality and that implies that every time you violate someone’s rights you’re you’re committing something immoral I don’t
think that that’s been established because now I do think that in most cases in almost every case violating a
right is also immoral but I don’t think it’s necessarily the case and the reason
is because you can imagine cases where you would you ought to violate
someone’s rights like if you had have to break into a cabin in the woods um which would violate someone’s
property rights you have to do that to save your your your child’s life uh you
could you could see a selfish person saying listen I I value my child’s life
more than the strangers property rights and so I’m going to do it and suffer the consequences and take the crime so I
don’t think that it’s necessarily the case now I do think there’s a connection I do think that morality is a guide to conduct and as part of that code of
conduct we need to know how to act with each other in terms of force and we need to know which laws and
which rights are Justified according to rational argumentation yeah well the
problem I have is you said earlier that I’m mixing politics and ethics and then you said that rights have nothing to do
with morality you kind of clarified that and said there’s a loose connection but the very concept of Rights is an ethical
political concept it’s defined as a just claim to something or a moral claim to
something well I don’t know I mean so so that’s that’s without morality there’s no such thing as rights I mean that’s
what rights are unless you’re coming up with a new idea of Rights in divorcing them from that but then you’re using a
word that’s traditionally meant one thing right different way these terms
have been used lots of ways and they’re I I simply I simply want to distinguish the concept of of morality from the
concept of of justice and rights um they they could be related I think they are related but there are different concepts
so morality is broader certainly it’s like Furniture you know all all all chairs
are Furniture but there’s furniture that aren’t chairs and morality covers more than just it is broader but again as I
said I’m I’m not persuaded that that rights are a subset of morality but
they’re an intersecting set um and that’s because I’m not sure that in
every case that it’s there’s a rights violation that the rights violation the
the rights would be acting immorally I’m not sure about that but morality takes place in a context right and and like
you said earlier that ran says that suicide is a preoral choice but that’s not actually what she says what she
actually says is that there’s some conditions under which it would be completely appropriate for somebody to commit suicide and there’s some
situations in which it wouldn’t context matters no I’m not so sure about that I mean on Rand I’m I’m talking about a
kind of an esoteric Point Rand Rand had to like I think Rand
instinctively and intuitively like you and I probably would say that a normal healthy person and a
normal context ought not commit suicide they ought to they ought to live according to their you know according to
their full potential in their life and that would not include committing suicide but she had to admit see because
Ran’s ethics are ultimately hypothetical and I think this is in it’s May you’ve
said hypothetical before but they’re not hypothetical it’s conditional and there’s a difference distinction but you
know the thing is and I I apologize because I’ve kind of let us maybe a little astray and I know you want to get to the IP stuff I don’t want to just
argue about objectivist ethics I just wanted to make the point that that that’s that’s not exactly what she said
and anybody that’s watching you can you know do you read opar or Google Rand no no I and I don’t think it’s I I just I
just think that Rand says that the source of morality is man’s choice to live right
yes and the Cho but the choice Live Well can it’s deeper than that though it’s not just his choice to live it’s the
fact that we have to make choices the very fact that we don’t come pre-programmed or with an automatic
guidance on how to live necessitates that we discover and use or morality totally agree but the point is when she
said it’s morality flows from the choice to live
at to to live as a man um proper to his nature um um this implies and I believe
she recognizes this this implies that you could you couldn’t have a moral criticism of someone’s choice not to
live because you have to already have made the choice to live which is what the
reason I say hypothetical is is all of Ran’s um you could call it conditional but all of Ran’s U moral structures are
based upon this fundamental choice to live which itself has to be premoral or a I can’t I think she said preoral she
says it’s a preoral choice she does and she also I mean it’s not Rand it’s Leonard peof in the endorsed course on
objectivism talks about suicide and and elaborates on it but I want to okay sort of get back to this rights thing because
outside of morality the only rights you have according to the way the word has been defined since at least Samuel
Johnson I are if the government is creating positive rights or or or civil
rights but that’s not how you’re using the term so outside of morality you don’t have rights there’s there’s
no it’s not just that they’re somehow intersecting or connecting rights are
literally the social implementation or the political implementation of moral
it’s how human beings need to live in society I think that’s that’s it’s fine
to look at it that way um I don’t strongly object to that okay so I want
to I I want to move on a little bit to the the value creation things because
you’ve said that value two things one is you don’t have a a right to the things
that you’ve created and you don’t have a right to value and that’s I think at the very core of your critique of
intellectual property so can you explain exactly what you mean by that right and
then I’ll if you want to chime in and give me what where you think sure what your perspective is um so um first of
all the randians used use the word value in a sort of idiosyncratic way they’ll say that you know the purpose of life or
one of the purposes in life is to you know have productive activity using our rationality according to our values
according to our nature to produce or create values like
they use they use the word values in the plural and like it’s a noun like there’s a thing that you’re creating that’s a
value but you know the austrians would say well value is
subjective in the sense not subjective in the sense of arbitrary like Rand criticized it with Kant but subjective
in the sense of being valued by the valuer um and value is not a thing that you that you can possess or own it’s
it’s more of an act of of valuing like demonstrated preference so as mises
would look at it when we act in the world and again this is compatible with with rational action according to
objectivism when we act in the world we find ourselves in a world of reality and scarcity and we have certain values and
we seek to pursue those values by using scarce re means of action to achieve those values we pursue a given end and
when we do that we demonstrate that we value the thing that we’re choosing that we’re pursuing and we demonstrate that
we value the intermediate means because they help us achieve the end so we value things so it’s a verb it’s not like a
noun we don’t create values we value things and when we create what we’re doing is we’re we’re we’re having
successful Human Action to achieve an outcome that we value or that we prefer
and sometimes that output is not just a state of affairs like one output of my action
might be just to to to achieve a state of affairs and the State of Affairs would be the end of my action like I
might want to make my girlfriend happy or I might want to see a movie that I’ve never seen or I might want to go to
Antarctica and see a sunset from there something like that I don’t acquire ownership of something
when I do those things I have a successful action um but I don’t acquire ownership of anything it’s a productive
successful action but I don’t do anything quite often though one subset of of action is the is the acquisition
or or or transformation of scarce resources so if I prefer to have a
hamburger or if I prefer to have a car one way to achieve that end would be to
purchase it from someone like to pay money money or to perform a service someone gives me title to that car or to
that hamburger now I have that so the end of my action was to acquire the ownership and possession of this thing
which I’ve done another thing we could do is we could transform or produce by
taking resources that are un untransformed and transforming them into
a better configuration rearranging as even IR ran recognizes we take existing
matter that we own or that someone else owns and we rearrange it with our effort
our mentality our creativity our labor into uh into another shape which gives
us a more useful thing that’s how we create wealth and what you could call a
value you say you’re creating values but what you’re really doing is you’re you’re making an existing thing more
useful to you or to someone else that’s how wealth and value um wealth emerges
from productive activity of human beings but what they’re doing is they’re using and manipulating existing resources to
make them into a different shape and then the only question is who owns these
things that were created or that were rearranged and property rights answers that question because property rights
already specifies by contract and by original appropriation who owns these scarce
resources this is why for example Henry Ford when he owns a factory making Model
T cars he he employs workers and they are in a sense helping
to cooperate to produce the cars because they’re using their effort their labor to transform the the raw steel and the
Rubber and everything that comes down the assembly line and produce new cars but they don’t own the
cars the Ford corporation owns the cars right because of contract between the people in fact this is part of the
problem with marxian ISM right and the idea that if the if if for makes a
profit it can only be because the Surplus labor value of the workers is being stolen from them or exploited
because they own their labor because marxians also buy into this labor theory of value which is similar to the labor
theory of property which is at the root of intellectual property thinking this idea that people own their own their
bodies and therefore they own their actions or their labor as some kind of substance which exudes from their bodies
and is mixed with these things and give the gives the transformed resource its
value and therefore there’s some kind of connection between owning your body and then owning your labor and owning the
resulting created value or thing so it’s all confused you simply need to say
everyone owns their body and they own resources that they acquired by contract or from the St state of nature and then
however they rearrange them using their labor the person who owns the outcome
the the resulting product depends upon the contract so if it’s if it’s Henry Forge workers they don’t own it because
they didn’t own the input factors if I take some wood some some logs from a
field that I acquire and I therefore Homestead them and I own these logs and I use my lab to build a log cabin I own
the log cabin but not because I created it I own the Log Cabin because I already owned the field and the logs now I have
a log cabin because my effort rearrange these logs into a more useful configuration called a house or a cabin
does that does that sort of make do you understand where I’m coming from why does that make sense I understand
completely where you’re coming from and I think you’re 100% wrong and I’ll tell you why the first thing is that let me
just start at the at the end where you said and I’ll give you my conclusion to what you what you said there and then I want to go back you said that you own
The Log Cabin because you own the resources I would say it’s both I’d say you own
The Log Cabin qua Log Cabin because you own the resources that went into it and
because you’ve created it that’s what I would say there now as far as value goes
part of this confusion and I I’ve actually written about this in my book part of the confusion comes from
different senses in which the term value is used it comes from Ran’s what I think is a bad definition of value so but let
me just start with misus so misus talks talks about how value is subjective meaning that there’s no intrinsic value
in any object or anything in life it’s all a matter basically of personal
opinion but if misus is right about that that’s why misus held there can be no
objective morality and he also held there can be no rights because without
morality you can’t have rights it’s why he said that you can only judge things from the outcomes that you want so he
advocated capitalism he would say if you want Prosperity if you want the greatest happiness for the greatest number this
is what you do but he didn’t put pass a moral judgment on that no I agree he he was he was a consequentialist I I view
his structure of his argument is similar to rans they’re both hypothetical in the sense of if you want this you should do
this okay now there’s a different there’s so when it comes to economics meaning prices
profits those things are the result of subjective choices they have nothing to
do with the right or wrongness of the decisions the the the the price of a given product my microphone has to do
with the value that the various participants in the market place on that microphone buyers and sellers so
economic value in that sense is subjective in that it’s the result of subjective decisions now when you use
value as a a verb like you said it’s true there’s a diff there’s a distinction between what I value and
what actually has value what has value is in the objective sense the problem
with Rand is Rand defined value is that which you seek to gain or keep yeah I think that’s a serious mistake because
it implies that value is subjective whatever I happen to gain or keep or or
or you know seek to gain or keep is a value but that’s definitely not the case because she said life is the standard
what that means is that I can value the wrong thing in other words I can value something that doesn’t have actual value
as measured against what you agreed my well-being my long-term
wellbeing I for instance can value heroin that doesn’t mean heroin has value and I totally agree with that and
I think value but value defined in the objective sense is any object or quality
desirable as a means or ends in itself that’s a that’s a different sense I I I
agree but and I don’t agree with you about so I think you’re wrong about mises I think you’re you’re inflating so
I think mises is perfectly correct to say that as a descriptive matter um
value as an economic phenomena is subjective but that does not imply the subjectivity the ethical subjectivity
that ran criticizes rightly um and it doesn’t imply it’s not says so Stefan
yeah says so I mean it’s it’s not we’re talking about mis’s view no actually I
mean if if morality is a code of values to guide human behavior in value vales
are all subjective then morality necessarily is subjective mises says as much I don’t remember I think he says it
in Human Action I don’t have it in front of but what his position is I don’t I mean we’d have to look at MIS I don’t
think mis’s that’s not integral to mis’s views on economics that was his political views I think they’re they’re
shaky they’re roughly Common Sense they’re roughly you know they’re
hypothetical you could pick apart his ethics he and he never did write a lot about ethics uh but his I think his his
economic view is simply look it’s it’s simply a fact I mean even Rand made this mistake to a degree if you think it’s a
mistake when she defined when she does Define value is something that you act
and she add the word act to gain and or keep agre very similar to that’s very similar to the economic notion of
demonstrative preference I don’t disagree and that’s why I’ve critiqued her definition I’ve done it both on this
podcast I’ve done it in writing and and I’ve done it when I’ve been interviewed elsewhere but that doesn’t negate the Crux of Theory right that’s just a poor
definition within a much larger system yeah and you and I probably see somewhat eye to eye on some of this but I don’t
really think it is relevant so how do how does that get you to okay let me ask you one hypothetical
see if we can distinguish here so I work for a company building log cabins yes
this log C and I I go to you know two houses a day I go to house one house two
and I I I work with 10 other guys and we we we get paid a salary and we take
these Log Cabin we take these logs and we build log cabins now we are producing the log cabins with our labor and our
effort why don’t we own those why would you say is the simple reason we don’t own the log cabins that we produce
because we didn’t own the initial resources exactly no but you have to have that’s why I’m saying in the terms in the cabin and I gave you the example
is it’s both it’s the fact that I own the resources and created it if you’ve
been farmed out to create something for somebody else with their resources you agreed under contract to do that right
that’s a different scenario but you would agree do it with your own resources fine but you would agree if I have a human being operating in the
world and I I have title to this tract of land and I own the trees on it I
already own those things correct yeah okay now if I build a log cabin I would
agree I’ve created something of value I I would agree you could even say I’ve created a value you can say I’ve I’ve
increased my wealth yes um now but the reason I own the resulting
house is completely explained by the fact that I already owned everything that went into it you don’t need to add
the second thing I own it because I own the the the lumber and I own what I
create you already own own it that’s that’s what I
understand you own you own you own these this matter that’s on your land and however it’s arranged you own it and
whatever you want to call it you own it that’s true sure but the problem here is that
as we as we discussed earlier if human consciousness is the source of rights which you agreed it was the nature of I
say Consciousness but well well the rational faculty the fact you have to choose that’s the human consciousness I
don’t think it’s a source of rights I’d say it’s it’s it’s it’s it’s just it’s the reason why we can justify rights but
okay so now if I take my my matter I’m I’m on my land and I take everything and
I build a cabin yes I’ve I’ve added by the by the creative rational faculty
that I have I’ve added to the value that was previously there in just raw
resources you’ve added what I call Wealth that’s correct you created wealth so you would not say that I don’t have a
right to that additional value I do I do you don’t no one has a right to Value okay well here I have a
hypothetical for you if I built this Log Cabin I take my raw resources and I
rearrange them and I build a log cabin so the value from of the raw resources on the market let’s say is $5,000 or or
hold on or the value to you like now it’s more useful to you it’s a more useful thing it it it’s useful to me but
there’s also a market value of the the product of there could there could be the logs right so now I rearrange them
into a cabin that has a market value say of $200,000 right okay if somebody were to
knock down my cabin yes and leave all the raw resources are perfectly intact
just like they were before right yes you could you wouldn’t just say well I don’t
know what you would say but I wouldn’t that all they’ve done is trespass my property and that’s why it’s a rights violation they would owe me not you
would say that they only owe you the value of the raw resources there’s two there’s two things you’re saying here I would say that yeah the only thing they
did was commit trespass against your property they use it without your permission that is true that’s what do
they owe you now for the additional value that you added by means of your creation of course but not because you
own the value well then so how why would they own you owe you anything if not
because prop because the reason that we we want there to be property rights and
the reason we object to property rights being invaded the reason we oppose aggression is because it has an effect
because we’re again we’re not ghosts right so if for example if you could if
you could destroy my log cabin and with a blink of an eye I could conjure it
back up again in other words if we lived in a world of no scarcity um then we
would even have we wouldn’t care if someone did it because they wouldn’t be doing anything the only reason that we care about an AC of aggression is
because it has an effect and the effect is that it prevents the owner from using his resource as he sees fit so if I want
my I don’t know let’s take a better example let’s say I’m a virgin virgin a
virgin teenage girl hold that one thought right there the the virgin teen because I want to address what you what
you just said about the the cabin all right