≡ Menu

KOL443 | Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Approach (PFS 2024)

Play

Kinsella on Liberty Podcast, Episode 443.

“Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Approach,” 2024 Annual Meeting, Property and Freedom Society, Bodrum, Turkey (Sep. 22, 2024). This was also podcast  at the Property and Freedom Podcast as PFP285. See: “Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Approach” (PFS 2024). Below please find the Shownotes provided by Grok, my own notes from which the speech was read, the transcript (cleaned up by Grok), and an Article version of the speech prepared by Grok (here: Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Libertarian Solution (Grok)).

Grok shownotes:

Shownotes: KOL443 | Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Approach (PFS 2024)

In this thought-provoking talk from the 2024 Property and Freedom Society Annual Meeting, Stephan Kinsella tackles the contentious issue of abortion through a libertarian lens, acknowledging its complexity and the deep divisions it creates. He traces the historical pro-choice leanings of libertarians, particularly Objectivists like Ayn Rand, while noting the rise of pro-life sentiments within modern paleo-libertarian circles, exemplified by the 2022 Libertarian Party platform change led by the Mises Caucus. Kinsella critiques both secular and religious arguments, dismissing Doris Gordon’s Libertarians for Life stance as overly simplistic and finding Walter Block’s “evictionism” convoluted, as it frames the fetus as a trespasser despite most pregnancies resulting from voluntary acts. Reflecting on his own evolution from a staunch pro-choice Randian to a more nuanced perspective as a parent, Kinsella grounds his analysis in the libertarian principle that rights stem from reasoning capacity, a concept rooted in Hans-Hermann Hoppe’s discourse ethics.

Kinsella argues that the abortion debate is intractable due to irreconcilable religious, feminist, and philosophical differences, making state intervention problematic. He proposes a “radically decentralist” solution: until birth, the family unit, particularly the mother, should have jurisdiction over abortion decisions, free from external legal interference. This approach, inspired by Hoppe’s 2011 remarks in Romania, avoids intrusive policing—such as monitoring pregnancies for late-term abortions deemed murder—and respects the private nature of family matters. Kinsella suggests that positive obligations may arise from voluntarily conceiving a child, akin to rescuing someone you’ve endangered, but maintains that legal systems should defer to families until the child is born, when homicide laws apply. He references Hoppe’s A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism to underscore that a born child owns its body, marking birth as a clear legal boundary.

This decentralist framework aligns with libertarian principles of minimizing state overreach and respecting individual autonomy, as Kinsella elaborates in his broader work, such as Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Papinian Press, 2023). The episode also points to related discussions, including Christos Armoutidis’ “Preargumentation Ethics and the Issue of Abortion” (J. Libertarian Stud., 2024) and Oscar Grau’s chapter in A Life in Liberty: Liber Amicorum in Honor of Hans-Hermann Hoppe (Papinian Press, 2024), for further exploration of libertarian perspectives on abortion. By advocating for family jurisdiction, Kinsella offers a pragmatic way to navigate this divisive issue, leaving listeners with a compelling case for decentralization in one of libertarianism’s most challenging debates.

***

Update: see Christos Armoutidis, “Preargumentation Ethics and the Issue of Abortion,” J. Libertarian Stud. 28, no.1 (2024): Abstract:

The issue of abortion—and, more broadly, the issue concerning the source of rights or, more precisely, when and why humans acquire or recognize rights—has long vexed libertarians. It’s a complex issue with numerous good-faith and reasonable arguments that lead to differing conclusions. This issue is usually brought up when the topic of abortion is discussed in libertarian circles. This article will attempt to show when and why humans get rights by advancing a theory inspired and implied by Hans-Hermann Hoppe’s “argumentation ethics”; it will then endeavor to “resolve” and present the consistent libertarian stance on the abortion issue.

and Oscar Grau, “On Argumentation Ethics, Human Nature, and Law,” in A Life in Liberty: Liber Amicorum in Honor of Hans-Hermann Hoppe, edited by Jörg Guido Hülsmann & Stephan Kinsella (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2024).

Panel discussion:

My speech notes:

Abortion: A Radically Decentralist Approach

Stephan Kinsella

Property and Freedom Society

2024 Annual Meeting

Bodrum, Turkey

September 19–24, 2024

Alright, let’s have as much fun as we can with a topic like this.

Contentious issues among libertarians:

  • Anarchy vs. Minarchy
  • Forms of state: monarchy vs. democracy
  • Open borders vs. mass immigration
  • Intellectual Property (we are winning this one)
  • Israel vs. Gaza
  • Ukraine vs. Russia

Abortion: Pro-choice and Pro-Life

  • I’ve changed my own mind a bit on this issue, after becoming a parent: from pro-choice. to more sympathetic to pro-life arguments, and to my current decentralist view
  • Traditionally libertarians have tended to be pro-choice, including virtually all Objectivists, though there were always some minority pro-life voices (e.g. Doris Gordon of L4L).
  • In recent years many seem to be more conservative, and more friendly to religion, and many more opposed to abortion than in the past.
    • The LP removed its pro-choice plank in Reno in 2022 as part of the Mises Caucus takeover, the “Reno Reset,” arguing that the issue is not settled and each candidate should be able to adopt their own position on this issue.
  • On some issues it seems possible to make progress. Many libertarians come from conservatism, or sometimes leftism, moving at first towards libertarian minarchism and then eventually to libertarian anarchism.
    • I changed my mind on the IP issue and have managed to persuade a large number of people to adopt the anti-IP position.
    • Views change on the issue of open borders and immigration and on particular issues like Israel vs. Gaza and Russia v. Ukraine.
  • But it seems almost impossible for anyone to change someone else’s mind on the abortion issue.
    • The fact that this issue seems intractable, often rooted in deep lifestyle preferences or religious beliefs, is relevant, I think to how this issue is best solved in a political-legal sense.
      • See Loren E. Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), p. 91: “The intractability of the dispute … may itself be philosophically significant.”

There are the well-known arguments

Pro-choice

  • There is the modern, or feminist, argument: it’s my body.
    • Of course the response is that there is a baby inside which complicates the matter
    • For this reason even most pro-choice people do not not favor legality until birth
      • Ayn Rand: “abortion is a moral right-which should be left to the sole discretion of the woman involved.” (“Of Living Death,” The Objectivist, Oct. 1968, 6)
      • In Rand’s view, opposition to abortion arises from a failure to grasp both the context of rights and the imposition that child-bearing places on women. As she put it: “A piece of protoplasm has no rights-and no life in the human sense of the term. One may argue about the later stages of a pregnancy, but the essential issue concerns only the first three months.”
      • So even Randians recognize difficulty in the later stages of pregnancy

Pro-life

  • Then there is the religious-based pro-life argument
    • As this is religious, it is not exactly rational since people of different faiths can have different beliefs about souls, life, rights, and so on

Libertarian abortion arguments

Pro-Life

  • Doris Gordon of Libertarians for Life: Pro-life
    • she was a neo-Randian and had a secular argument against abortion.
    • However it ultimately was a cheap semantic argument about what it means to be “human”.
      • It’s a simplistic argument, as all semantic arguments tend to be
      • Doesn’t account for rights of non-humans, e.g. intelligent space aliens
        • Since it makes “being human” the standard for rights
        • Why would intelligent aliens have rights? They are not human
      • Why don’t animals have rights?
      • What is it about humans that gives rise to rights, and why to fetuses necessarily possess the features that gives adult humans rights?

Pro-Choice

  • Walter Block’s “evictionism”: Pro-choice
    • Somewhat convoluted, to my mind
    • Not clear whether it’s pro-life or pro-choice
    • Seems to be pro-choice in today’s world with our level of technology
    • Basic argument: All humans have rights, by virtue of being human.
      • “We maintain that the fetus is an alive human being from day one onward, with all the rights pertaining to any other member of the species.” Walter Block & Roy Whitehead, “Compromising the Uncompromisable: A Private Property Rights Approach to Resolving the Abortion Controversy,” Appalachian L. 4, no. 2 (2005): 1–45
      • So far it’s similar to the argument of Doris Gordon
        • Semantic
        • Problem for both arguments: ignores what it is about human nature that gives rise to rights
        • It can’t just be “human genes”
        • What about intelligent space aliens? Wouldn’t they have rights?
      • This includes unborn fetuses since they “are also human”
        • “If a fetus is not a human, what is it? A monkey?”
      • So all humans have human rights, including baby humans and unborn humans (fetuses)
      • And yet the fetus is a trespasser
        • Block has convoluted arguments as to why the fetus is not invited, which is one of the arguments I have made
        • I have argued that the fetus is not a trespasser since it’s invited
          • More on this later—
        • The fetus, as a trespasser may be evicted, but only by the gentlest means possible
        • Unfortunately in today’s technology it is not possible to evict the trespassing fetus without killing it
        • So the pregnant mother is permitted to kill the fetus in order to evict (remove) it, even though its death is a side effect of this eviction process
        • Presumably if technology improves in the future and the mother can remove the fetus without killing it, she would have to do this and would not be permitted to kill the fetus
          • Left unanswered are questions such as: suppose the mother could have the abort the child with a normal noninvasive procedure that kills the fetus, or she could remove the fetus by C-section without killing it, but she would have to undergo anesthesia and serious surgery. Can she only evict the fetus via C-section, or may she use the less invasive procedure that ends up incidentally killing the baby?
          • It would seem that if the mother was able to remove a fetus without killing it but only via invasive surgery, she would still have the option to use a less invasive method which would kill the fetus
          • So in the end “evictionism”, though is poses as a pro-life theory still ends up supporting the right to abort
        • One aside: in my recent debate with Walter about voluntary slavery (KOL442), Walter says that if a couple pays a surrogate to have their baby, then they can force her not to abort since she has partially sold her body to them; I suppose a husband could do the same with his wife. So only in the case of women voluntary enslaving themselves can abortion be prohibited. Make of this what you will.
      • Other arguments:
        • Sharon Presley and Robert Cooke, “The Right to Abortion: A Libertarian Defense,” Association of Libertarian Feminists (2003?)
        • Doug Bandow, “Abortion: No Libertarian Triumph,” Chronicles (2007)
        • Rothbard: See comments by Robert M. Whaples, in “A Vision of a Productive Free Society: Murray Rothbard’s For a New Liberty” (part of a symposium in the Spring 2024 issue of The Independent Review (Vol 28, no. 4) dedicated to Murray Rothbard’s For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto)
          • “The shortcomings of this point of view are compounded in his discussion of abortion. “If we are to treat the fetus as having the same rights as humans, then let us ask: What human has the right to remain, unbidden, as an unwanted parasite within some other human being’s body?” (121). The tyrannical coercive government is a parasite and now a defenseless fetus is placed in the same category. The crucial word in this sentence is unbiddenPlasmodium falciparum, the protozoan parasite that causes malaria, is certainly “unbidden,” but portraying a baby this way will strike many readers as perverse or worse. The fetus had no existence and was “bidden” into existence by the actions of his or her mother and father in almost every case. At best, this is a major blind spot in Rothbard’s thinking about the “no harm” principle.”

My View

  • I was originally pro-choice but now that I’m a father I am not so callous about it and to think abortion is increasingly immoral the more developed is the fetus.
    • In my view, rights are a status that emerges from the possession of reason and the capacity to argue
      • It is not “being human” but rather having the nature that most adult humans share: reason
      • This approach is general enough to also handle the case of other intelligent species such as space aliens or other animals
        • But distinguishes humans from other non-sapient animals
      • Thus born children clearly have human rights
      • Hoppe, TSC: “… the ownership right stemming from production finds its natural limitation only when, as in the case of children, the thing produced is itself another actor- producer. According to the natural theory of property, a child, once born, is just as much the owner of his own body as anyone else.”
      • Whether late-term fetuses have rights is a harder question
        • Appears to be a “continuum issue”
      • In my view it seems reasonable to conclude that early-term fetuses do not have rights since they only have the potential to develop reason
        • late-term fetuses are similar to babies and thus have whatever rights babies have
      • Note: To the extent late-term fetuses have rights, this means they are not trespassers, contra Block
        • They are instead invited
      • On Positive Obligations:
        • In my view, libertarianism does not oppose “positive obligations” or positive rights, but only unchosen positive obligations
        • If you see someone drowning in a lake you have no positive legal obligation to try to rescue them
          • This is not to say there is not a moral obligation
        • But if you push someone into a lake you incur a positive obligation to rescue them because your action created their peril and situation of need
        • Likewise babies are naturally helpless and parents have created this situation of need and dependency by procreating
      • So: If and when the fetus can be said to have rights then we can say one of the obligations of the parents is not to kill the fetus
        • Other positive obligations such as support
          • one reason I am sympathetic to the civil law doctrine of forced heirship
          • Better for the parents to be required to support their children than the community or the state
        • So in my view, a good argument can be made that late-term abortion is very similar or tantamount to infanticide
        • For most people such a conclusion means late-term abortion should be treated as a crime
          • Is this the case?

Intractability

  • There are both pro-life and pro-choice arguments
    • Pro-life: religious
      • the pro-life view that abortion is murder from conception is either based on religion or faith, or flawed semantic arguments (Doris Gordon’s “Libertarians for Life” that “humans have human rights because they are human”)
    • Pro-choice: Feminist, Randian, Evictionism
      • The feminist pro-choice view ignores the fetus’s rights and usually is pro-life in the later stages of pregnancy
      • Block’s evictionism is confused
        • It is also based on the “humans have human rights” argument
        • Yet it characterizes fetuses as trespassers even though they are invited
      • Reason-based rights arguments such as mine will also be rejected by those holding the other views
    • The argument seems to be uniquely intractable

Unique Status of Pregnancy

  • In addition we must recognize that there are several difficulties with treating abortion as a crime like murder or infanticide
  • A born baby is an independent person and can be protected by the same laws that protect other born humans
    • By contrast fetuses are fully dependent on the mother and not yet quite part of the moral community
    • “rights claimed for fetuses, children, or the mentally incompetent … must necessarily be urged on their behalf by others if they are to be pressed at all.” (Lomasky, p6)
      • All this means that when the legal system extends its protection to members of society, especially the dependent who did not create and do not enforce the legal and justice system, there needs to be good reasons to do so.
      • They are not automatically entitled to it.
    • “I shall offer an account of basic rights that is multivalent. By doing so I hope to avoid the troubles that plague theories of rights purporting to find in all rights holders some one essential property vouchsafed by nature (or Nature) such that it, and it alone, guarantees the possession of rights. Most, but not all, adult human beings are project pursuers. Therefore, they have reason to accord to themselves and to other project pursuers the status of rights holder. Unless there were project pursuers, there could be no basic rights. However, project pursuers are not the only holders of rights. Others, young children for example, also enjoy that status. They do so in virtue of the social relations to project pursuers in which they stand. They, as it were, piggyback on project pursuers. The development of this argument is found in Chapter 7.” (p. 40)
    • Birth marks a quantum leap forward in the identifiability of human beings. … participation in social relations that constitute one a recognizable individual for others takes a dramatic turn at birth. Before that event one exists in relative anonymity. … Birth is the transition from anonymity to public standing. … birth marks an abrupt alteration, not in some internal property but with respect to external relationships. It is the single great discontinuity that breaks what is otherwise a smooth curve. Therefore, it stands out as the indicated demarcation point constituting inception of membership in the moral community.” P.197–98
    • “both law and common morality do recognize birth as a pivotal moral event. Although abortion has historically been regarded in some quarters as an offense, it is almost invariably accounted a different offense than infanticide.” P.198
  • Policing infanticide is not radically different than policing normal homicide, but policing fetuside or abortion would require massive privacy and monitoring intrusions
    • How are outsiders even to know that a woman is pregnant if she keeps to herself and stays her own home?
    • Is she to be liable if she has bad health or eating habits and has a miscarriage? 
    • Doesn’t she ha ve enough to worry about already?
    • If there is a difficulty in the pregnancy and difficult choices to make who is better to make them other than the mother, her husband, and her doctor?
    • Is it the purpose of law to police unborn humans who have not yet become independent beings and fully integrated into the moral community?

The Decentralist Approach

  • Any legal system only has limited jurisdiction
    • The US has no jurisdiction over abortion policy in China
    • Texas has no jurisdiction over abortion policy in California
    • Even private legal systems have limited jurisdiction
      • Restricted to the locale, not worldwide, as a practical matter
    • Given the intractability of the abortion issue and given the unique status of the fetus as not quite yet a member of the moral community, given its dependence on its mother and family, and given the unique situation faced by the mother and the family’s unique and intimate role in this, given the difficulties of determining “continuum issues”, the obvious and best solution is simply to recognize that only the mother and her family have jurisdiction over this issue 1
    • If the family permits abortion and fails to “outlaw” it, that can be criticized just as Texans can criticize China’s abortion laws even though they have no jurisdiction over it and it’s simply not their business
    • Recognizing the family’s right to decide these matters does not mean that an abortion is “okay” it simply means it’s no one else’s business, and not the jurisdiction of an external legal system or community, whether the state or a private legal system
    • The “legal system” of a family that does not prohibit abortions can be criticized and ostracized, but the external community’s legal system should not have jurisdiction to reach it, until the child is born
    • This solution will not satisfy everyone but given the intractable nature of this issue, no one’s solution will
      • At least this approach is the most decentralized and the most compatible with reality and with a MYOB approach

Hoppe’s Decentralist Approach

  • I’ve been pondering this issue for almost 30 years
  • I dimly recalled Hans urging me to tackle this issue many years ago
  • In reviewing my notes, I realized that not only did he urge me to do this but that his own solution is the one that has finally occurred to me as the obvious one
  • One of my letters indicated I had a long phone call with Hans in Aug. 1995 about this issue, 29 years ago.
    • Hans suggested the best solution would be for the extended family to be equipped to mahe the decision about the appropriateness of an abortion, not the government, and not even the local community, as the family is best equipped to judge these things and it’s no one else’s business.
    • In 2011 I taught the Mises Academy course KOL158 | “The Social Theory of Hoppe: Lecture 6: Political Issues and Applications; Hoppe Q&A”.
      • In the final lecture I fielded Q&A with some input from Hans
      • My view: the more developed is the fetus the more immoral it is, until at a certain point is becomes more than just immoral and is aggression. Where to draw the line precisely is not possible,
      • and in any case, any legal prohibition on even late-term abortion would require either a police state or such intrusion into the private family life that it is not acceptable.
      • Therefore, even if we say that some late-term abortions are tantamount to infanticide, it is likely that this would not be prohibited legally in a free society. In essence, the legal system would put “jurisdiction” for such decisions at the family level itself.
      • Hoppe: “I essentially agree with you, and would emphasize in particular the counter-question: even if we grant that there might be something wrong, morally and/or legally, who is entitled to go after the mother? Who is the victim? Certainly not the state or the ‘public at large.’”
        • Hans’s input for (July-Aug., 2011), around 25minutes in, slides 18–19; youtube
      • Later that year, Hans spoke at The Ludwig von Mises Institute of Romania (November 8­-11, 2011)
        • Hoppe in Romania
        • Questioned about children, abortion, the state’s role and guardianship rights, Hans replied that abortion should be a family matter, not one for the state to be involved in.
        • This implies support for my view that even the local and external justice community has no jurisdiction.
      • I have put off this request by Hans for 29 years but I trust now he sees I have dealt with it as best I could.

Two concluding comments:

  • I was reared Catholic, attended Catholic schools for 12 years, was an altar boy—so Guido, please forgive me
  • Now that I have solved the difficult issue of abortion, I’m going to work on exempting Bitcoin from capital gains tax.

YOUTUBE TRANSCRIPT as cleaned up by Grok

Libertarian Perspectives on Abortion: A Jurisdictional Approach

Transcript of a talk by Stephan Kinsella at the Property and Freedom Society, 2024

Good morning. It’s a testament to the dedication of libertarians that you’re here early on a Sunday, ready to discuss complex issues like abortion after topics as esoteric as interest rates in a hypothetical world. Unlike anarchy or intellectual property—where libertarians often find consensus—abortion remains a deeply divisive and challenging topic. Today, I’ll explore common arguments, libertarian perspectives, and propose a jurisdictional approach to this intractable issue.

The Complexity of Abortion

Abortion is uniquely difficult because it’s rooted in deep-seated beliefs—religious, philosophical, and personal. Unlike issues like taxation or war, where libertarians often align, abortion resists easy answers. Everyone has an opinion, and changing minds seems nearly impossible. My own views have evolved over time. As a former Randian, I once dismissed the fetus as “just a clump of cells,” staunchly pro-choice. But as a parent, I’ve grown more sympathetic to pro-life arguments, though I remain critical of both sides.

Libertarian Views on Abortion

Historically, most libertarians, particularly Objectivists, have leaned pro-choice. Ayn Rand, for instance, argued that a “piece of protoplasm” has no rights, emphasizing the woman’s autonomy, though she acknowledged complexity in later pregnancy stages. However, there have been exceptions, like Doris Gordon, a secular, Rand-oriented libertarian who founded Libertarians for Life. Gordon argued that fetuses, as humans, possess rights—a view I find overly simplistic, as it hinges on semantics rather than reasoning capacity.

In recent years, the libertarian movement has seen a shift. The rise of paleo-libertarianism and the Mises Institute’s influence has brought more pro-life voices into the fold. In 2022, the Libertarian Party’s Mises Caucus removed the pro-choice plank from its platform, arguing that the party should remain neutral on such a contentious issue. This change sparked debate, with pro-choice libertarians feeling alienated, but it reflected the growing diversity of thought within the movement.

Common Arguments: Pro-Choice and Pro-Life

The pro-choice argument often centers on bodily autonomy: “It’s my body, and the government shouldn’t interfere.” Yet, the presence of a fetus complicates this stance, as it’s not solely about the woman’s body. Ayn Rand’s view, while pro-choice, admitted that late-term pregnancies pose ethical challenges, suggesting the first trimester is less contentious.

Pro-life arguments, often religious, assert that life begins at conception, granting the fetus full human rights. While not inherently irrational, these arguments struggle in secular debates, as they rely on faith-based premises that don’t resonate universally. This makes dialogue difficult, as religious and secular perspectives rarely find common ground.

Libertarian Arguments: Evictionism and Beyond

One notable libertarian perspective is Walter Block’s “evictionism.” Block argues that a fetus, as a human, has rights but is also a “trespasser” in the mother’s body. Thus, the mother can “evict” the fetus, even if it results in death due to current technological limits. This view, while appearing pro-life, effectively justifies abortion, making it pro-choice in practice. However, Block’s argument falters when considering that most pregnancies result from voluntary actions, not trespass. His response—that a fetus can’t be “invited” because it doesn’t exist pre-conception—feels convoluted and unconvincing.

Block’s evictionism raises further questions. If technology allowed a fetus to be removed safely mid-pregnancy, would a mother be obligated to choose that over abortion? What if the safer option, like a pill, is less invasive than a C-section? These complexities highlight the theory’s practical shortcomings.

A Personal Perspective: Rights and Reason

My view starts with the premise that rights stem from our capacity for reason and argumentation, as articulated by Hans-Hermann Hoppe’s discourse ethics. Adult humans possess rights due to this capacity, which a young fetus lacks. While a fetus has the potential for rights, it doesn’t yet meet the threshold. However, as pregnancy progresses, the fetus develops, and by infancy, rights are undeniable. Somewhere along this continuum, a line must be drawn if we’re to consider certain acts, like late-term abortion, as crimes.

As a parent, I find early-term abortions for trivial reasons increasingly troubling, though I don’t believe they should be illegal. The moral and legal questions diverge, and libertarianism’s focus on negative rights—obligations not to harm—complicates the issue. Yet, I argue that positive obligations can arise from voluntary actions. If you push someone into a lake, you’re obligated to help them. Similarly, conceiving a child, a voluntary act, creates a dependent being, potentially imposing obligations on parents, including not terminating its life if it possesses rights.

A Jurisdictional Solution

Given the intractability of abortion debates, I propose a jurisdictional approach, inspired by Hoppe’s insights. Abortion is unique due to its private, familial nature and the diversity of beliefs surrounding it. No universal consensus exists, and imposing one risks authoritarianism. Just as Texas has no say over California’s or Turkey’s abortion laws, the state should have no say over a family’s decisions until the child is born.

Until birth, the family unit—particularly the mother—should have jurisdiction over abortion decisions. Once born, the child is subject to homicide and infanticide laws, but prior to that, external legal systems should stay out. This approach respects the private nature of pregnancy and avoids intrusive policing. For instance, if late-term abortion were deemed murder, enforcing such a law would require invasive surveillance, as pregnancies can be concealed. Moreover, holding mothers liable for miscarriages due to negligence—like smoking or tripping—would place undue burdens on pregnant women.

Hoppe himself endorsed a similar view in 2011, arguing that abortion is a family matter, not a state concern. This hands-off approach aligns with libertarian principles, prioritizing individual and familial autonomy over state intervention.

Conclusion

Raised Catholic, I understand the emotional weight of this issue, but I believe a jurisdictional approach offers the best path forward. By leaving abortion decisions to families until birth, we respect diverse beliefs, avoid state overreach, and acknowledge the unique complexity of pregnancy. Having tackled this issue, I’ll now turn my attention to exempting Bitcoin from capital gains tax—a lighter challenge, perhaps.

Thank you.

  1. A somewhat analogous argument is made in favor of the right to free speech even when the speech in question is false–the speaker himself has to be the one with the right to decide. As the judge in a recent case regarding Florida’s censorship of speech, the judge wrote: “The government cannot excuse its indirect censorship of political speech simply by declaring the disfavored speech is ‘false.’” Or, as he quoted Justice Robert H. Jackson: “The very purpose of the First Amendment is to foreclose public authority from assuming a guardianship of the public mind through regulating the press, speech, and religion. In this field every person must be his own watchman for truth, because the forefathers did not trust any government to separate the true from the false for us.” Dahlia Lithwick & Mark Joseph Stern, “Federal Judge Shoots Down Ron DeSantis’ War Against Free Speech“. It is also analogous to the right to self-defense: even when the law bans vigilante justice and “self-help” an exception is always made for self-defense when the cops are not available. []
Share
{ 7 comments… add one }
  • Pavel September 24, 2024, 8:21 am

    Stephan, thank you for this. Your logic very much resonates with my own moral intuition. I have a question though. You write: “The “legal system” of a family that does not prohibit abortions can be criticized and ostracized, but the external community’s legal system should not have jurisdiction to reach it, until the child is born”. You highlight “until the child is born”. Now, for the sake of argument, let’s imagine that the child is born, and it is born with some defects which in this particular community are considered very bad omen (albino?), and the family believes that the child needs to be sacrificed to their gods immediately. So, they collectively commit infanticide in accordance with their community beliefs. Their (small) community approves of the act. Does the “wider” community (which objects) have the right to interfere? Is this already-born baby “a part of the moral community”? Is the “the state or the ‘public at large” a victim in this case, or is it more like “China is not Texas jurisdiction” kind of situation? If late-term abortion prosecution is an unacceptable intrusion into the private family life, then why infanticide protection is acceptable? (Basically, why is it someone else’s business?). Or, to make the same question significantly broader –if a libertarian community discovers a community of cannibals (de facto another radically decentralised jurisdiction) who regularly eat members of their own community (and them only) — do the libertarians have the right to interfere?

  • Stephan Kinsella September 25, 2024, 9:54 pm

    If we agree that a born baby has rights, then yes killing it would be murder or infanticide and yes I think outsiders could interfere to protect the infant. It doesn’t at this point require invasive monitoring of the woman’s pregnancy.

    “Or, to make the same question significantly broader –if a libertarian community discovers a community of cannibals (de facto another radically decentralised jurisdiction) who regularly eat members of their own community (and them only) — do the libertarians have the right to interfere?”

    I would say so.

Leave a Reply

© 2012-2025 StephanKinsella.com CC0 To the extent possible under law, Stephan Kinsella has waived all copyright and related or neighboring rights to material on this Site, unless indicated otherwise. In the event the CC0 license is unenforceable a  Creative Commons License Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License is hereby granted.

-- Copyright notice by Blog Copyright