From my recent TLS post: Stephan Kinsella, “Corporate Personhood, Limited Liability, and Double Taxation,” LibertarianStandard.com (Oct. 18, 2011). Reprinted below.
Also cross-posted at Mises; archived comments below. Comments from the TLS version are also reprinted below. See also this Grok conversation about shareholder liability and extending D&O insurance to cover shareholders.
See also:
- Mercadente, The Illiberal Nature of Limited Liability: A Libertarian Critique
- Recent Grok conversation (appended below)
- Libertarian Answer Man: Legal Entities and Corporations in a Free Society (Feb. 29, 2024)
- Classificationism, Legislation, Copyright
- The Over-reliance on State Classifications: “Employee” and “Shareholder”
- Libertarian Answer Man: Corporations, Trusts, HOAs, and Private Law Codes in a Private Law Society (Nov. 11, 2023)
- KOL418 | Corporations, Limited Liability, and the Title Transfer Theory of Contract, with Jeff Barr: Part II (Aug. 18, 2023)
- KOL414 | Corporations, Limited Liability, and the Title Transfer Theory of Contract, with Jeff Barr: Part I (Aug. 11, 2023)
- KOL211 | Corporations and the Corporate Form (April 28, 2016)
- KOL170 | Tom Woods Show: Are Corporations Unlibertarian? (Jan. 24, 2015)
- KOL100 | The Role of the Corporation and Limited Liability In a Free Society (PFS 2013) (Sep. 22, 2013)
- Stephan Kinsella on Limited Liability (2013), Reported by Sean Gabb (Oct. 6, 2013)
- KOL 026 | FreeDomain Radio with Stefan Molyneux discussing Corporations and Limited Liability (Feb. 28, 2013)
- Rothbard on Corporations and Limited Liability for Tort (Feb. 7, 2010)
- Left-Libertarianism on Corporations and Limited Liability (Jan. 24, 2011)
- Pilon on Corporations: A Discussion with Kevin Carson (Oct. 26, 2009)
- Limited Liability, Paleo-libertarianism, Left-Libertarianism: Recent Posts and Debates (Dec. 12, 2008)
- Defending Corporations: Block and Huebert (Sep. 9, 2007)
- Legitimizing the Corporation and Other Posts (Aug. 6, 2009)
- Corporations and Limited Liability for Torts (Dec. 10, 2008)
- Stephan Kinsella, Sean Gabb’s Thoughts on Limited Liability (Sep. 26, 2006) (49 archived comments; also posted below)
- Thoughts on Limited Liability by Sean Gabb (2) (Jan. 8, 2008)
- This was in the aftermath of the first meeting of the Property and Freedom Society: see Sean Gabb, The Inaugural Meeting of the Property and Freedom Society: An Incidental Record, Free Life Commentary, Issue Number 148 (June 14, 2006)
- Stephan Kinsella, In Defense of the Corporation (2005) (re Piet-Hein van Eeghen’s article “The Corporation At Issue, Part I”)
***
Stephan Kinsella, “Corporate Personhood, Limited Liability, and Double Taxation,” LibertarianStandard.com (Oct. 18, 2011)
The politics of the left-oriented Occupy Wall Street (OWS) movement, like that of the right-oriented modern Tea Party movement, is not very well defined. But one of the things some of the OWS participants are calling for in their list of “demands” is an end to “corporate personhood.” In this they echo the views of left-libertarians who contend that state-chartered “corporations” are the source of grave social ills. [ See vol. 20, no. 1 and vol. 19, nos 3-4, of the Journal of Libertarian Studies, focusing on these and related issues, in particular articles by, and in response to, Piet-Hein van Eeghen’s anti-corporation views, and Kevin Carson’s views on mutualism. ]
Some of these issues were recently debated on the pages of Roderick Long’s blog, in the comments to his post “Double Standard.” Left-libertarians who oppose incorporation, and usually also “capitalism,” argue that firms derive some great benefit from the state by the privilege of incorporation. The standard leftist critique of the corporation is the “concession” theory outlined by Robert Hessen in his seminal study In Defense of the Corporation (see a key excerpt from Hessen corporation tort liability excerpts). They argue that the state grants to corporations three features: entity status, perpetual duration, and limited liability to shareholders, all of which are artificial and would not exist absent state intervention. Left-libertarians maintain that these privileges grant corporations more power than they otherwise would have, which distorts the market, nay, society in general. This gives rise to more “hierarchy” and “authoritarianism” than would prevail in what Hans-Hermann Hoppe calls a private law society, and indeed, to “exploitation” of the workers by the bourgeoisie.
The Alleged “Privileges” of Incorporation
Labor Theory of Value
There are several problems with the left-libertarian and leftist critiques of corporations. One is the acceptance of a Marxian-type labor theory of value—the idea that employers per se “steal” or exploit from workers the “social surplus product”—a discredited, hoary, unscientific view based on deeply flawed economics.
Entity Status
And as Hessen has pointed out, each of the three corporate features pointed to as a state-granted privilege—entity status, perpetual duration, and limited liability for shareholders—can be created purely by private contract. As for entity status (being able to represent the firm in lawsuits or for property ownership purposes, in the firm’s name) this is just a convenient legal fiction that could be created by means of trustees, or other contractual techniques (including agreements with private defense agencies, insurance companies, arbitral agencies, and the like). In any case, even stripped of this procedural convenience, firms could still organize themselves as joint stock companies or “corporations”.
Perpetual Duration
Hessen also easily disposes of the myth that perpetual duration is a privilege granted by the state; this can be achieved easily by means of continuity agreements and the like.
Limited Liability
The big objection to corporations is usually limited liability for shareholders. Now first let me mention that many non-attorney critics of this notion seem confused about what it means (and many attorneys also misapprehend it). They think the doctrine insulates a tortfeasor from liability even if he was negligent, so long as he is a shareholder. Or that the doctrine exempts managers and officers of the corporation from liability for torts of others. They are wrong. The doctrine merely says that shareholders are not jointly and severally liable for all the debts of the company that they have a share in. If a company that A owns shares in is sued and driven to bankruptcy, A loses the value of his shares but is not personally liable for the lawsuit against the company. (N.b.: to the extent some state incorporation statutes also limit the liability of managers for torts of the corporation, and not just that of passive shareholders, this is another matter and is more objectionable. However, the primary purpose of limited liability laws is to protect the shareholders from general liability; and in any case, officers and directors are routinely protected from any personal liability by the use of D&O insurance.)
Second, we have to distinguish here between contractual debts, and debts arising from torts (or even intentional crimes). As for the former, this is easy to dispatch: someone loaning money to, extending credit to, or engaging in a contract with a corporation is implicitly agreeing to pursue only the assets of the corporation itself in case of a claim, not the personal assets of shareholders (unless it insists on some shareholders personally guaranteeing a loan or contract, as if often the case for smaller companies).
So what about torts? The typical example is a truck driver for a company who negligently harms an innocent third party. The third party has no contract with the firm, unlike in the case of contractual debts noted above. The opponent of corporations maintains that the victim should be able to sue not only the employee-tortfeasor, and the corporation itself (to go after its assets and deep pockets, including its insurance policies), but shareholders themselves. After all, they are the “owners,” and should be liable too. Right? And thus, state limited liability provisions are short-circuiting the liability that shareholders would normally have. This lowers the cost faced by corporations; it makes shareholders less responsible in their decisions about who they elect for the firm’s board of directors; it lets the firm externalize costs onto the market.
The problem with this theory is the assumption that in a private law society, “shareholders” should be vicariously liable for the negligence of others. There is, in fact, no libertarian justification for this view, as libertarian theorists such as Robert Hessen, Murray Rothbard, and Roger Pilon have argued. [See Roger Pilon’s Corporations and Rights: On Treating Corporate People Justly, which has some very good stuff on why limited liability does not give any special privilege to shareholders; also my posts Legitimizing the Corporation and Other Posts; Rothbard on Corporations and Limited Liability for Tort; Defending Corporations: Block and Huebert (archived comments); Pilon on Corporations: A Discussion with Kevin Carson; Corporations and Limited Liability for Torts (archived comments); In Defense of the Corporation; also my comments (archived) to “Jeff Tucker’s post Scrupulosity and the Condemnation of Every Existing Business“; and list of resources on this in Sean Gabb’s Thoughts on Limited Liability (archived comments). ]
In this situation, some employee of a firm has committed some tort—a negligent act (such as a FedEx truck driver negligently crashing into some victim). Here the victim has a right to sue the negligent employee-tortfeasor. The question is: Who else’s assets can the victim go after? Can he sue the managers, or the directors, or go after corporate assets, or sue shareholders?
We have to recognize that the prima facie answer—the default condition—is no: each person is responsible only for his own torts, not for those of others. To hold someone else liable requires some kind of “vicarious liability” theory. To do this, you need a theory of causation and responsibility, which Pat Tinsley and I have tried to sketch out in Causation and Aggression. Yes, you can be jointly responsible with the actions of others if you engage with them in cooperative action to cause the illicit result: for example co-conspirators in crime, a gang of bank-robbers, and so on.
But holding employers—or shareholders—vicariously liable for actions of their employees relies on the offensive, paternalistic, feudalistic concept of respondeat superior—a master is responsible for his slaves’ or servants’ transgressions. As Hessen notes, this is just a vestige of the medieval mentality. Why would a shareholder be liable for actions of some employee? There are two aspects to being a shareholder that could conceivably give rise to vicarious liability for another’s direction actions. First, the shareholder may have contributed capital (money) to the firm. On the other hand, he may not have: he may have bought the share from a previous shareholder. This latter possibility is routinely overlooked by those who blame the shareholder for contributing money to a company that has an employee who commits a negligent act during the course of his employment. They assume that giving money to the corporation is akin to “aiding and abetting” it, so that the shareholder is responsible for all its debts that it incurs as a result of actions it engages in with the “aid” of the money contributed by the shareholder.
But contributing capital to a firm is nothing more than aiding it, which co-employees, customers, creditors, vendors, and suppliers also do. If you broaden causal responsibility so much that you would implicate a shareholder just because he gave financial aid to a firm (though as I noted, not all shareholders give money to a firm), then employees, customers, creditors, suppliers are also all liable, which is obviously absurd.
Second, the shareholder may have a vote in electing directors. But then again, he may not; not all shares are voting shares. Further, the shareholder might not exercise his right to vote; and if he does, he might vote against the directors who win; and even if his choice wins, his vote is almost never decisive; and, in any case, rarely is it the case that the director campaigns on a platform of directing managers to permit employees to engage in torts and negligence. These latter qualifications are rarely noted by corporate opponents who blame shareholders for corporate actions simply because they have a right to vote. But possessing a right to vote for directors does not obviously imply vicarious liability for torts committed by employees hired by officers appointed by those directors. In fact, the right to control property does not automatically imply responsibility. If I own a knife and it is stolen by a thief, I am not guilty of murder if the thief kills someone using the knife, even though I still own it. Ownership implies the right to control. It does not imply liability. Liability flows from actions, whether those actions employ means owned by the actor or not. In other words, whether one owns a means employed in an act of aggression is irrelevant. Likewise, having an ownership (control) right does not automatically imply responsibility. [ See my posts The Libertarian Approach to Negligence, Tort, and Strict Liability: Wergeld and Partial Wergeld and The Non-Aggression Principle as a Limit on Action, Not on Property Rights; also IP and Aggression as Limits on Property Rights: How They Differ. ]
(A related point is that shareholders are not even “owners” of corporate assets in the same way that I own a knife. The state legally classifies shareholders as owners, but we have to be wary of relying on state classifications. [ See my post The Over-reliance on State Classifications: “Employee” and “Shareholder”. ] The shareholder can influence board composition by vote, and has a right to receive dividends if paid, and some pro rata right to receive part of the assets of the corporation upon liquidation, but a Google shareholder doesn’t have the right to use the Google headquarters or corporate jet.)
What this means is that if you attribute vicarious responsibility to the shareholder merely because he has a vote—that is, he has “some influence” on who the directors are—then everyone who “influences” the firm is also potentially liable for torts of its employees—again, as in the case of holding people liable for aiding and abetting a firm, this can include creditors, who can influence company policy or board composition, employees and their unions, important suppliers, and the like. Again, this is obviously absurd.
The kneejerk and simplistic rules that would implicate shareholders for torts of employees based simply on the fact of ownership, voting, and contributing capital, would also render hundreds, thousands, maybe tens of thousands of people jointly and severally liable for the negligence of Pepsi truck drivers. This is obviously not a result compatible with libertarian theory.
So it seems that a shareholder who is truly passive and does not manage the affairs of the firm, nor make management decisions or direct the actions of employees, should not be liable for torts committed by such employees. Why should he be? Hessen, Rothbard, and Pilon are right.
It is important to recognize this because opponents of state incorporation claim that the state’s grant of limited liability to shareholders is a huge privilege granted to them that would disappear if the state were to get out of the business of granting corporate charters. In fact, here the state and the left-libertarians share the same presupposition: that absent state incorporation privileges, shareholders would be vicariously liable, via respondeat superior, for torts of employees of companies the shareholder owns stock in. The state uses this false claim to justify regulating the company; the left uses this false claim to exaggerate how much benefit existing state-chartered corporations must be receiving, and to predict that a state-free world would look vastly different, and that our current “capitalist” order is dominated by the state and not really free at all.
Likewise, as already mentioned, another fallacious view shared by the state and the left-libertarian opponents of incorporation is the idea that a corporation cannot exist unless the state grants it the privilege of “legal personality,” i.e. makes it a separate legal entity. The state makes this claim to hold itself out as the firm’s benefactor, and claims the right to place conditions on this grant—various regulations, etc. And if it’s a separate legal person or entity, why, gosh!, it owes income taxes! It’s a person, after all, isn’t it? And the left-libertarians join in this refrain by claiming that state incorporation grants the legal entity privilege to corporations, and they could not exist without it. Some privilege, that subjects you to regulation and income taxation! So: we can see that the state’s fallacious claim that it is granting a privilege of legal personhood to the corporation is used to justify double taxation: first, the corporation, as a “legal entity,” is subject to corporate income tax; then the shareholders are subject to capital gains or income tax when they receive dividends. Effectively, the shareholders are double-taxed. Some privilege.
But this view is confused too. As Hessen has explained (see previous references), a company having a “corporation”-like structure could arise on a free market using private contract alone. It could sue in “its own name” (as a convenience); it could have perpetual life; contractual debtors could go only against the corporate assets and not those of shareholders, since they agreed to it; and victims of torts of employees of the free-market “corporation” could sue the employee-tortfeasor but not the shareholders, since they are not causally responsible for his torts any more than the customers are.
Ending Incorporation
In any case, we can agree with the left-libertarians that the state ought to stop granting incorporation status. Contractual firms would arise—I don’t know if they would be called corporations, joint stock companies, limited liability firms or what—and the state would have less justification to subject them to income taxation—to impose double taxation on shareholders. Firms would be far better off—and shareholders would still have natural limited liability. What’s not to like?
Why left-libertarians think corporate status is some net “benefit” to every firm in the Fortune 500 (again, see the comments to Long’s post “Double Standard”) is a mystery to me. Removing SEC “public company” regulations (which cost each public company about $3–4M a year) and removing corporate income tax alone would be a huge boost to American capitalism. So what if the name of the standard form of organization changed? Small price to pay.
In sum, yes, get rid of state corporate chartering, and the corporate taxation and regulation that accompanies it.
For some more discussion of these and other ideas, see my post Capitalism, Socialism, and Libertarianism; I also discuss some of these issues in Episode 133 of This Week in Tech.
Appendix: Corporate America being “part of the state” and the calculation problem
(Update to this section: see also: Left-Libertarians on Corporations “Expropriating the Efforts of Stakeholders”; Is Macy’s Part of the State? A Critique of Left Deviationists; and my comments in response to Kevin Carson’s claim that “there’s probably some fraction of income over $250k that was really earned through hard work and enterpreneurship.” in “I’ve Never Seen a Poor Person Give Anyone a Job”.)
Some final comments. Note that the left-libertarians’ confused adoption of the state’s underlying rationale for monopolizing, regulating, and taxing corporate-firms causes them to conclude that the US economy is basically dominated by companies that are in reality parts of the state. Instead of viewing only some firms as closely in bed with the state—defense contractors, say—they view virtually all of corporate America as agents of the state. Even a Walmart or Apple are thought of as parts of the state—in a fascist sense, that is: they are nominally private but really parts of the state because of the various state “benefits” and “privileges” these companies receive. (See my post Apple vs. Microsoft: Which Benefits more from Intellectual Property?) Walmart benefits—maybe disproportionately—from state subsidies to highways etc. (though the local mom n’ pop shops ship things in from far away too). Nevermind the corporate taxes and SEC regulations. It “benefits” from the “privilege” of the state grant of entity status (which it does not need to exist, as Hessen shows) and from exempting its shareholders from general liability from torts of employees (which they do not need since they would not be personally liable anyway in a free society; and which could be taken care of easily anyway by a simple and cheap extension of D&O insurance; and which the corporation usually has sufficient assets to handle in any case).
Take Walmart: the left-libertarian thinks it is unlibertarian (in a “left-thick” sense) because it has bosses and hierarchies that allows it to “boss people around” in ways it could not get away with on the free(d) market. It is only able to get away with these thick-libertarian oppressions and exploitation because of the net benefit and privileges it gets from the state. The non-left-libertarian agrees Walmart and other companies’ structure etc. is distorted because of the state but sees no reason at all why a Walmart of some type could not exist on the free market—in fact, I would think it highly likely Walmart could do even better, shorn of the costs the state imposes on it too. (That is not to say that there would not also be more local, small, diverse companies, more self-employment, more self-sufficiency, more early retirement. The free market would be rich and diverse.) Even an Apple Inc., which now does benefit in some ways from patent and copyright law that it uses to suppress competition, could exist and prosper, by selling high-end hardware, like the Mercedes of computers—even if it would be less able to stop clones or maintain its closed model.
In the recent debate on Roderick Long’s blog, some of the left-libertarian commentators imply that virtually every one of the top 500 public corporations in the US is illegitimate, and part of the state. This of course implies that many others are too, and even that a vast swath, if not most, of the US economy is effectively part of the state. Now I’ve detected this implicit view before, and I’ve (informally, in blog posts and comments) observed one problem with this view is that it implies that the apparent “capitalist” prosperity we see is all a mirage. (See Is Macy’s Part of the State? A Critique of Left Deviationists.) This is because, if you accept Mises’s calculation argument, a centrally run economy cannot be economically prosperous. If most of corporate America is “really” part of the state, then the calculation argument means we must be in a USSR-style shambles, despite appearances to the contrary. Sure, I realize the GDP measure has methodological problems, and that the state exaggerates and propagandizes, but what’s more plausible: that we are really all poor, living in a 1970s Soviet-Style morass with just faked prosperity (hey, maybe we never made it out of the Malthusian trap in the 1800s after all; maybe the whole Industrial Revolution is a mirage!); or that there is actually a vast amount of prosperity generated by the underling genuinely free market economy despite the state’s depradations? As far as I can see, the left-libertarians have to argue the former; I think most sensible libertarians will take the latter view.
The former view is what results from the idea that most state corporations are “net beneficiaries” of the state. As the state cannot produce wealth but can only destroy it, if the bulk of US enterprise is a net beneficiary of the state it must come from the remainder of society, meaning an overall impoverishment for everyone—meaning the apparent prosperity and productivity of the last 20, 50, 200 years is a mirage. Simply declaring “hierarchical” firms that have a corporate charter “net beneficiaries” of the state is obviously the wrong criterion, since it leads to absurd results: it leads you to deny the evidence of free market generated prosperity that is before our eyes. (This may be one reason Kevin Carson objects repeatedly to my Misesian calculation argument along these lines.) Obviously we need a more selective way of determining whether a given firm is a net beneficiary of state aid or not. It has to be a minority of firms—otherwise we would be living in a USSR-style third world shambles. A firm that is heavily dependent on something that would not appear the same way in a free society would be suspect, such as the military defense contractors. Firms heavily dependent on subsidies, or IP (like Microsoft), would be more suspect than others, but even here, Microsoft provides a useful product, albeit at prices inflated by its copyright monopoly. It may not be possible to develop rigorous criteria, but why do we need to? We have systemic and economic reasons—plus common sense and experience dealing with many firms in society that obviously do more harm than good—to doubt the claim that most of corporate America is a net beneficiary of the state. Hell, most of us even think that individual humans who rise to the top of power, like Barack Obama, are harmed in a deep sense by achieving “success” and power the way they do.
Update: See David Henderson’s EconLog post, Hummel on Moss on Limited Liability, and Jesse Walker’s 2001 Reason post, Killing Corporations.
UPDATE:
-
Murray N. Rothbard: A foundational figure in modern libertarianism, Rothbard supported the concept of limited liability for shareholders in corporations, particularly in the context of torts committed by corporate employees. He argued that shareholders should not be vicariously liable for actions they did not directly control or commit. In his view, liability should rest with those who actively manage or perpetrate a wrong (e.g., corporate officers or employees), not passive investors. This perspective is evident in his discussions of property rights and voluntary market arrangements, where he saw limited liability as a natural outcome of contractual agreements rather than a state-granted privilege.
-
Robert Hessen: A historian and libertarian scholar, Hessen wrote In Defense of the Corporation (1979), a seminal work defending the corporate form, including limited liability. He argued that limited liability does not depend on state intervention but emerges from private contractual arrangements. Hessen posited that shareholders’ limited liability for corporate debts and torts reflects the principle that individuals should only be held accountable for their own actions, not those of others (e.g., employees or managers) unless they directly authorize or participate in them. His work aligns with libertarian ideals of free markets and personal responsibility.
-
Roger Pilon: A legal scholar and libertarian associated with the Cato Institute, Pilon has defended limited liability as compatible with libertarianism. In his article “Corporations and Rights: On Treating Corporate People Justly” (1979), he argued that limited liability is not a special privilege conferred by the state but a logical extension of freedom of contract. He emphasized that shareholders’ agreements to limit their liability to their investment is a voluntary arrangement that does not inherently violate others’ rights, aligning with libertarian principles of non-aggression and mutual consent.
-
Walter Block: A prominent anarcho-capitalist and economist, Block has co-authored works defending corporations and limited liability, such as “Defending Corporations” with J.H. Huebert (2004). Block argues that limited liability is a market mechanism that facilitates investment and economic growth, consistent with libertarian emphasis on free markets. He rejects the notion that it unfairly shields shareholders, asserting that liability should follow causation and control, not mere ownership, and that creditors and others can adjust their dealings with corporations accordingly through voluntary contracts.
-
Sean Gabb: A British libertarian writer, Gabb has engaged with the limited liability debate, notably in his “Thoughts on Limited Liability” (2006). While he expresses some reservations about its application, he defends it as a practical and libertarian-compatible institution in a free society. He suggests that shareholders’ limited liability reflects their lack of direct control over corporate actions, placing responsibility on managers or employees who make operational decisions, which resonates with libertarian notions of individual accountability.
{ 26 comments… read them below or add one }
October 18, 2011 at 7:41 pm
-
This is some tasty and strong stuff, brother.
October 19, 2011 at 9:07 am
-
Kinsella: “The problem with this theory is the assumption that in a private law society, “shareholders” should be vicariously liable for the negligence of others.”
Let’s not use the word “shareholder.” Let’s call the stockholder what he is: the (or, an) owner. There is nothing vicarious about the damage caused by the (an) owner of anything, whether it be a dangerous pit bull or a dangerous corporation, such as a nuclear-power generating corporation.
Kinsella: “We have to recognize that the prima facie answer—the default condition—is no: each person is responsible only for his own torts, not for those of others. To hold someone else liable requires some kind of “vicarious liability” theory. ”
The pit bull can’t pay, so his owner is responsible. Same with the owners of corporations. No need for any “vicarious liability” theory because there is nothing vicarious about the relationship nor the liability of an owner for his pit bull or her corporation. There is no “vicarious liability” theory involved because there is no “someone else.” There is only the owner.
Kinsella: “But holding employers—or shareholders—vicariously liable for actions of their employees relies on the offensive, paternalistic, feudalistic concept of respondeat superior—a master is responsible for his slaves’ or servants’ transgressions. As Hessen notes, this is just a vestige of the medieval mentality. Why would a shareholder be liable for actions of some employee?”
What is offensive is this is that this statement is deceptive and utter nonsense. The agent-principal relationship is alive and well in law and in relationships recognized as such throughout the world. It is ancient, of course, but most truths are, and modern lawyers are as unable to refute them as were their medieval predecessors down through the ages. Why didn’t the author or Hessen use this modern, non-offensive, non-paternalistic, non-feudalistic term? And since you repeat the same unjustified assertions over and over, let me also be repetitive: We are not talking about a “stockholder” liability for “some employee,” what the author is talking about is an owner’s responsibility for his or her potentially dangerous property or operation. The author would incise the owner from his property, but the ownership of property (viz., private property) is crucial to every libertarian theory I have ever encountered.
Kinsella: “On the other hand…he may have bought the share from a previous shareholder. ”
This is a silly argument. Whether one bought the pit bull as a puppy or a trained fighting dog is immaterial to our owner’s relationship to the property.
Kinsella: ” They assume that giving money to the corporation is akin to “aiding and abetting it…”
This is a strawman, one of so many in this article that I can’t even begin to count them let alone address them all. For this one let me just say, no one need assume anything of the sort, and I doubt anyone so assumes. No owner (stockholder) of a business “gives” it money. An owner either creates the business by an initial investing, or buys it as a going concern. Obviously how ownership is obtained has no affect whatsoever on the pit bull’s behavior nor on whether or not the reactor core melts during a tsunami. Nor does this point have any place in a *rational* argument. Like the argument in total, it is a lawyer-like attempt to ameliorate if not eliminate the personal responsibility involved in human action upon which liberty utterly depends.
If I were to characterize the argument in this article, as it characterizes any imagined opposing view, the kindest thing I could say is that it is silly. Not only is personal responsibility compatible with libertarian theory, it is the ultimate foundation of liberty. The author’s attempt to relieve owners of responsibility for their pit bulls or their dangerous operations engaged in for profit is essentially an attack on individual liberty in the manner of a lawyer defending a losing cause with one frivolous argument piled upon another until the judge finally orders her to “shut up.”
I could pick the rest of the article apart straw man by indirect ad hominem aimed at whoever might have the temerity to oppose this sanctimonious view, but suffice to say again that the only “vicarious” relationship is a figment of a creative imagination. And if my counter to this diatribe should be characterized as left-libertarian, I would have to classify this article as pure statist, but that would be adopting the methodology of this author’s endeavor to oppose personal responsibility and the individual liberty resulting therefrom.
There are other good reasons why corporations, which are purely products of State legislation, are harmful to liberty not addressed by the article. One big one is the so-called “legal fiction,” which holds that corporations are “persons” for the purpose of standing in legal proceedings. As a direct result of this fiction, many court rulings (including those of the Supreme Court) have been made in cases wherein the parties were the State and a corporation which established important precedents, which precedents were later applied to cases involving the State and individuals as though the latter were equivalent to corporations and without the human rights that can only be claimed by individuals. An example of this is the famous case of Brushaber vs. Union Pacific Railroad (http://laws.lp.findlaw.com/getcase/us/240/1.html), in which SCOTUS declared that the newly enacted federal income tax did not violate the Constitution as claimed in that case and therefor Union Pacific must pay it. From then (1916) until the present, that case has been cited in lower federal courts as having determined that the income tax was constitutional. It has been cited as precedent to deflect thousands of cases of individuals who have tried to challenge the constitutionality of the income tax as applied by the IRS against them, even though Brushaber never even considered the constitutionality of the income tax as applied to real individuals who are not legal fictions created by State legislation.
The State and corporations are so intimately tied to one another that defending the latter is virtually defending the State and its illicit powers, without which no corporation has ever existed.
October 19, 2011 at 10:41 am
-
Ownership of a pit-bull is more akin to owning a (potentially leaky, probably perfectly safe) propane tank than it is to partial ownership of a stockholding company. You yourself referred to the principal-agent relationship, the asymmetrical nature of which arises primarily because the latter commands faculties and resources unavailable to the former. This does not characterize an owner and his pet, which has (obviously) little by way of personhood but still generates liabilities for its owner. Tracing negligence from dog, which has no purposeful, rational action in the Misesian sense, to owner, who presumably does, is a trivial matter; establishing a causal relationship between (to use Kinsella’s example) the Pepsi driver and stockholders of Pepsi is not so trivial. This is not to suggest that liability is not, in some tenuous, circuitous manner, traceable, only that the claimant would encounter greater difficulty in trying. I can see a case being made for holding the employer responsible, and by extension, Pepsi Co., if the driver’s history or particulars about his habits are unearthed of which his superiors can credibly be shown to have been aware, or have overlooked. Perhaps the regional manager directed freighters to overload Pepsi fleet vehicles by an amount just above the optimal weight for safe braking distance. This seems actionable. However, this is a far cry from holding Pepsi’s boardmembers, and then stockholders, liable of same, beyond the diminished flow of rent by holding stock in a company now party to litigation. The relationship is there, but the existence of purposeful action on the stockholders’ part, bringing about an undesirable outcome, is not apparent.
Which cuts to the heart of my contention with this whole line of thinking. This seems to me more of a continuum problem, and more justifiably handled by the courts on an ad hoc basis rather than (as now exists) blanket immunity or (as Netterville suggests) enforcing total liability against all parties, regardless of participation. If the claimant can establish a causal relationship of purposeful action, bully for him; I doubt he can in any meaningful way, beyond the flow of capital and rent between the primarily responsible and the putative, peripheral parties. But I wouldn’t wish entirely to close off or open up the potential for liability.
The points you bring up regarding legal precedents are well taken, and I’ll read more about it—I’d love to see a response from Mr. Kinsella. Off the top of my head this seems moot if only because courts also find against individuals and thereby set unlibertarian precedents. The recent Angel Raich case comes to mind. A contentious issue like income tax, especially given the judicial activism surrounding its passage, would doubtlessly have found safe harbor in any number of cases. I’m not suggesting this particular case was not ultimately harmful, or that the modern conception of taxation does not turn on this decision, but merely that some court, somewhere, would doubtlessly have found in favor of the federal income tax, and that case would now serve as the precedent. Would the outcome have been materially different if textbooks instead referred to a conceivable case for the constitutionality of income tax withholding in which the court found against Vivien Kellems? I don’t know. We can’t say.
Thanks for the food for thought, both you and Mr. Kinsella. I am so novice about all of these concepts, I can really only bring up the untutored layman’s perspective and try clarifying my own position. I just wish the rhetoric weren’t so acerbic.
October 19, 2011 at 5:41 pm
-
D. Storey, Thanks for engaging. See my reply to Wildberry below, which I think responds to you comment as well.
October 19, 2011 at 11:20 am
-
Ned,
I can see this has gotten you fired up, but your understanding is a little shakey.Rarely have to rushed to the defense of Kinsella, but I think you are not deriving your criticisms from a correct understanding of the principles being discussed.
Shareholders are not employees, agents, or owners. They are shareholders, whose liabilities and powers are statutorily defined at the outset. Now you come along and want to change the nature of that in retrospect, not what the shareholder bargained for.
Your interpretation of vicarious liability is backwards, because the shareholders are neither employers or employees; they are investors whose proprtionality is a measure of share price.
A pit bull owner is liable for the tort of the Pit Bull, because it is the owner’s tort, negligence, which is at issue. The owner is not liable because of VL theory making the owner out to be the employer of the dog.
Also, an employee is not liable for the torts of the employer, and the employers is not liable for the torts of employees unless they are within the scope and course of their role as employee.
Shareholders are not “employers” precisely because they cannot exercise any control over the scope and course of the corporation, other than to vote and/or ratify materials acts of the BOD. They cannot ratify something that is illegal in the first place. The BOD controls the Executives adn the Executives control the employees. Shareholders buy in or sell off. That’s it.
I enjoyed your rant, but it would be helpful if you departed from some solid understanding of what you are criticising.
October 19, 2011 at 2:48 pm
October 19, 2011 at 6:15 pm
-
Wildberry, I’m sorry to have put you in a boat with Mr. Kinsella, which I know must be unconfortable–because, among other good reasons, his boat is about to sink even further when I respond to his silly, pit-bull rejoinder, in which he couldn’t resist attacking you as well. However to address your concerns directly:
“Shareholders are not employees, agents, or owners. They are shareholders, whose liabilities and powers are statutorily defined at the outset. Now you come along and want to change the nature of that in retrospect, not what the shareholder bargained for…Shareholders are not “employers” precisely because they cannot exercise any control over the scope and course of the corporation, other than to vote and/or ratify materials acts of the BOD. They cannot ratify something that is illegal in the first place. The BOD controls the Executives adn the Executives control the employees. Shareholders buy in or sell off. That’s it.”
Wild, you make my case. (As an aside, keep in mind, that the agent-principle relationship undoubtedly predates the state and human laws as does the ownership of private property. I believe both of these assertion can be deduced from the action axiom as Menger deduced that money predates the State, and, although I am neither an “economic anthropologist” nor an ethnologist, I doubt if there is any conflicting empirical evidence to the contrary.) The point is that before the State or in the absence of the State and its step child, the corporation, there was no such thing as a “stockholder.” There was the owner, responsible for his or her property. The corporation with its shareholder-owner, like the State itself, is a means of dispersing that all-important self-responsibility upon which liberty depends. Now if you’ll excuse me, I have to fit Mr. Kinsella with a new rectal orifice.
October 19, 2011 at 1:05 pm
-
If I own a single $23 share of GM stock, the victim of a defective GM car should be able to seize my house? Nonsense.
D Storey makes an excellent point:
“Perhaps the regional manager directed freighters to overload Pepsi fleet vehicles by an amount just above the optimal weight for safe braking distance. This seems actionable.”In this case, the principal had direct control over the circumstances that resulted in injury. If the pit bull analogy has any weight at all, it is here. The pit bull owner has complete and direct responsibility for the dog at all times. If the dog injures someone, the owner is rightly held liable because of his negligence. The shareholder, however, has no direct involvement in the actions of employees, and therefore have no liability under this standard.
Aside from direct involvement, as I recall, the principal is only held liable when the agent injures someone while performing duties within his scope of employment, or if the agent was only able to injure another party because of the means supplied by the principal. I.E. a truck driver crashes a company vehicle while making a delivery, or a hotel employee robs a guest. In the first case, the driver was performing his duty (and using means supplied by the company), and in the second, the hotel provided the employee with access to the guest’s property. In both cases the principal is only liable because he supplied means that were misused or abused. This is where shareholders bear some liability, and it is entirely appropriate that this liability is limited to their contribution/stake in the firm. If a Pepsi driver gets drunk and crashes, the principal’s relationship to the injury is strictly commercial. The means that were supplied that occasioned the injury were strictly commercial. So, it’s entirely appropriate that, when the principal had no direct involvement in the injury, that his liability be limited to his contribution to the injury. Strictly speaking, you might say the liability is limited to the truck itself, but since the entire commercial operation is interdependent, it’s appropriate to expand liability to the entire commercial operation. It is not appropriate, however, to expand liability to the personal property of the principal when that personal property was not involved in or tied to any property that was involved in the jury.
To what extent should shareholders be liable when they have no direct involvement in the tort? The extent that they supplied means to facilitate the injury, which is their stake in the company.
October 19, 2011 at 2:43 pm
October 19, 2011 at 12:57 pm
-
I own a little over a share of Wal-Mart stock (big investor that I am!) and yet I have no control over Wal-Mart property, employees, or policy (or I should say, no more control than any other customer can exert). Why should I be out more than the value of my share if Wal-Mart executives or employees do something wrong or objectionable?
October 19, 2011 at 1:12 pm
-
Likewise, why should you be held liable if you hire a trader to make investments on your behalf, and she buys a single share of Wal-Mart stock without your knowledge.
Likewise, why should you be held liable if you work for a company that offers a pension that includes stock in Wal-Mart, but you have no direct involvement in the investment decisions being made on your behalf, other than your continued willingness to work for your present employer.
October 19, 2011 at 1:06 pm
-
The heretofore analysis has been narrowly confined to tort exposure.
Is there any consideration of shareholder gains that directly result from fraudulent corporate activity? E.g., Distillery XXX has been selling watered down booze and paying handsome dividends as a result. Are the shareholders’ earnings available to pay claimants in a class action suit brought by defrauded customers? Is the decline in price of Distillery XXX shares as a result of the de-capitalization of the corporation due to settlement payments just recompense for shareholders’ fraudulent gains?
This seems to be the area where “liability” is most murky. Is the concept of “fraudulent conveyance” applicable, or are shareholders shielded from such exposure?
October 19, 2011 at 4:48 pm
-
Crickets. . . . ?!
October 19, 2011 at 5:59 pm
-
@jasontgordon October 19, 2011 at 1:06 pm
Would you hold the investors that Bernie Madoff swindled liable for his fraud?
Fraud woud apply to them only if they knew Bernie was a crook and relied on that knowledge in making their decision to invest.
Those that lost money don’t have to pay a penalty to others who also lost money. But those that did make money might have to disgorge their profits which may be used to pay restitution to those who lost, but not because they are liable in the way you are thinking of it, but becasue they were unjustly enriched by the fraudulent conduct of Madoff.
Liability is murky where the facts are murky. But for fraud to apply, someone has to knowingly deceive someone for the purpose of getting some of their stuff. Shareholders are not fraudulent by accepting dividends that as far as they know, are legitimate.
October 19, 2011 at 9:57 pm
-
not because they are liable in the way you are thinking of it
I don’t have a clue how or what you presume to be my thinking regarding investors, am I not clearly referring to shareholders?
So according to you Wildberry, dividends based upon fraudulent profits are justifiably owned so long as the shareholder accepted them in good faith? Give me a break. That logic would be convenient for a buyer of stolen goods, would it not?
Are shareholders in an actionable position to obtain damages related to their being payed dividends obtained fraudulently?
***
Comments from the TLS version:
68 thoughts on “Corporate Personhood, Limited Liability, and Double Taxation”
Comments are closed.
***
Stephan Kinsella, Sean Gabb’s Thoughts on Limited Liability (Sep. 26, 2006) archived comments:
{ 49 comments }
September 26, 2006 at 10:55 am
-
Groan – a great long response thrown right back at me.
I shall need to go away and think about these matters.
I shall also think about the best way of continuing the debate. I hate little more than interleaved replies. I much prefer the sort of deabte in which each response is complete in itself – rather like the three made so far.
September 26, 2006 at 11:17 am
-
I actually have a lengthy discussion of this issue in a word format that I’ve been unable to post in a decent way. Quick summary is that agency law is a major source of liability for sole proprietors, but is arbitrarily cut off in the case of shareholders merely by invoking the statutory grant of incorporation. One can argue that the corporate veil can be pierced, but the standards are not the same; in essence, so long as the shareholder is extremely negligent in how the business is run, he’s insulated from responsibility. In contrast, agency law places a burden on a sole proprietor to be responsible about his choice of agents.
I also agree that there is nothing wrong in theory about limited liability for contractual debts. The problem is that corporations, as they exist now, are statutorily created privileges, and not a creature of common law. The idea of a fictitious person is the source of much confusion and misapplication of fundamental principles. It would be far better to just call it what it should be – contractually limited liability, and move on.
September 26, 2006 at 11:43 am
-
Here:
“[Incidentally: I am actually not sure whether modern corporate limited liabilty does prohibit a victim of a tort done by personnel of a company from suing shareholders–if he could somehow establish the shareholder played a role.”
is the key. It does, so long as the shareholder can demonstrate that he “respected the corporate identity.” So, as long as he didn’t mix and mingle assets, or fail to hold corporate meetings, he’s protected from liability. In fact, so long as he colludes with his fellow shareholders, he can make it airtight by demonstrating that after all corporate formalities were followed, they all voted for the same result. In this case, they are all enforcing their own claim to having respected the corporate personality, thereby benefitting all of them equally.
In contrast, a sole proprietor who turned the day to day operation of his business over to a hired manager would be bound by the acts of his agent that were taken in the scope of the agency, period. The sole proprietor is responsible for choosing that person and imbuing him with authority. Especially if he didn’t supervise the manager very well and the manager uses the business to defraud customers. It doesn’t take much to see that a sole proprietor could be held liable for his negligence in such a situation. In contrast, the shareholders are actually encouraged to take LESS care in how the day to day manager is operating the business. The less care he takes, the more he can claim he respected the corporate personality.
It doesn’t mean that he will always be held liable when the agent acts negligently in the scope of the agency, but he can be. And that is more than can be said about shareholders, so long as they obey the rituals set forth in business incorporation statutes.
September 26, 2006 at 12:30 pm
-
This reminds me of immigration debate: what would we do if the state didn’t exist. Corporations are creatures of the state and as such are imbued with as much potential for evil as any other creature of the state. As Van Eghan pointed out in his wonderful papers, the state creates this artificial being to which managers owe a duty of loyalty and from which shareholders are owed some undefined right. The ultimate arbiter of what is “good” for the corporation is….the State!
Having litigated corporate issues from small to large, from local to international, it amuses me still to depose managers who have no idea what a corporation is.
The corporation question is a prism through which we discern pressing issues of liability, contract law and business organizations. That said, there’d be no “secretary of state” office to file “incorporation” papers in Libertania, and the so there is no issue of whether corporations as we know it would exist. They couldn’t. Just like in Libertania there would be no “immigration question.”
That said, would corporations exist in Libertania? For sure, because certain humans desire to cheat, steal and lie, and there is no better mechanism to achieve this ends than a corporation. “Give me money and I will give you this piece of paper that allows you to vote for candidates for board of directors once a year.” Very similar to “Delegate to me your rights and I’ll let you vote once every two or four years.”
Great bargain! As Mencken said, no one has gone bust underestimating the intelligence of the American people. September 26, 2006 at 12:33 pm
-
Would or could a corporation exist sans the state? In a true free market, the answer would be no. Stockholders could not limit their liability and erect an alter ego, i.e. corporate personhood. Corporations, as we know them today, are creatures of the state and are part and parcel of the state. If the state ceased to exist, corporations would die with it.
Thus, I would have to say that libertarians would have to reject corporations on principle.
Certainly, that would radically alter business, but capitalization would still be possible for very large companies. People could form old fashioned joint stock companies, the stockholders being fully liable of course. For people who wished to avoid liablity, they could capitalize via debt instruments. Entrepreneurs will find a way, they don’t need our help and certainly don’t need governments hindrance.
September 26, 2006 at 12:42 pm
-
Stephan: You may be surprised to learn I agree with what you’ve posted here. I want to add a few things:
Along the lines of creative alternative financial instruments to get the benefits of stock ownership while cutting the responsibility for decisionmaking for minority shareholders would be something like this: The corporation could issue “variable bonds” that give payments (coupons) in exactly the amounts dividends would, but give no voting rights until you own a notable amount of them (say, 1% of the total outstanding). Then, at least minority shareholders can’t be said to have “control” over the corporation. Index fund buyers could keep the returns and you could takeover just the same.
A lot of the opposition to incorporation is grounded in the idea that, conceivably, the corporation could commit a tort, and someone “connected” to the corporation’ management could be insulated from liability after assets are liquidated. However, it’s unclear exactly what the limits on this are. Presumably, individual shareholders should be allowed to “insure this away”. But then what if the insurer can’t pay? Is it settled then?
Also, opponents of incorporation are remarkably inconsistent. Yes, it’s true a corporation could commit a tort it couldn’t compensate. But then, so could most poor people today. It’s unfair in my eyes to act like corporations are evil for this, while poor people still roam the earth without some huge liability insurance policy, putting others at risk of being victimized but not able to compensate them.
September 26, 2006 at 12:50 pm
-
Lee: I’d advise against referencing the Van Eghen paper. It was painful to read because of the twisted logic. If there’s a point you want to take it, I’d recommend remaking the argument in your own words so as to save us the time.
Mark_Brabson: You have to be careful about the problem of meaning vs. reference, i.e., “Oedipus wanted to marry Jocasta, not his mother!” I think it would be more precise to phrase your position as being that libertarians are against incorporation, not “corporations”. Your position is basically that corporations as managed today could accomplish the exact same things through different financial instruments. Therefore, your critique of current corporations is the far weaker claim of “You should structure your financial arragements with different names.”
By the way, the term is “without”. No one’s impressed by your ability to pepper your posts with French.
September 26, 2006 at 12:53 pm
-
Person:
My opposition to corporations doesn’t spring from my views on torts. It springs from the simple fact that corporations are NOT of the marketplace, but are of the state. As a Libertarian, I must oppose distortions of the marketplace by the state, so by principle I must oppose corporations. No inconsistenties in my position. I can’t speak for others, of course, just myself.
September 26, 2006 at 1:05 pm
-
I am not sure one French term constitutes peppering.
Now mises.org, they are peppered with foreign words.
September 26, 2006 at 1:37 pm
-
The nominal reason for the invention of the corporation was to limit the financial liability of investors to what they put into the corporation. It was an asset protection scheme at its conception.
Although it quickly became a device for shielding investors from criminal liability, that was not its theoretical foundation. The operation of modern corporations isolate owners from being responsible for all kinds of malfeasance, but there is no moral basis for granting such protections. The classic two-level arrangement of an LLC owning a corporation to shield a sole propietor or partners from any legal action is reprehensible since it is obvious that the purpose is to act in any manner desired with impunity.
Corporations can and do defraud lenders and investors. People should loan or invest money carefully when dealing with a non-entity since its purpose is to shield real people from being financially liable. Corporations can and do empower agents to commit all manner of criminality and malfeasance.
But corporations do not commit crimes; people commit crimes–using corporations! Anyone who can be shown to have authorized or perpetrated a crime should be liable and punished. That includes officers, employees, agents, shareholders, lenders, or anyone else no matter what their relationship.
September 26, 2006 at 2:07 pm
-
Person:
“Also, opponents of incorporation are remarkably inconsistent. Yes, it’s true a corporation could commit a tort it couldn’t compensate. But then, so could most poor people today”
Person, here are two more important foreign terms to wrap your mind around so you can see your analogy is less than meaningless: de facto and de jure.
Poor people can’t compensate, but are still held liable. Shareholders may or may not be factually able to compensate, they are just legally insulated from liability regardless of their ability to pay.
Your whole argument, as usual, is a red herring. The question is, are corporations, as they currently exist, the product of principled legal reasoning, or are they the product of privileges granted by the state. Step one: Read the statutes on every state’s books that create them. (hint, that actually answers the question).
Now, as noted above, contractually limited liability is nothing novel – it is explicitly a matter of contract law. No libertarian should be against it being legal (although there are certainly arguments against the wisdom of buying into certain business arrangements). Further, it does provide a bit of a shorthand to what would otherwise require up-front disclosure during every contract negotiation – however, that’s such a minor point that it really is no big deal.
On the other hand, it’s really clear to anyone who spends more than 2 minutes actually researching the concepts of agency law and piercing the corporate veil that corporations currently provide statutory privileges that go beyond any common law privilege against tort liability.
Do I think it’s a major impetus behind current incorporation? No – quite likely, the contractually limited liability is the driving force. But that doesn’t somehow magically change the fact that corporations do enjoy state granted privileges that are not fundamentally sound.
September 26, 2006 at 2:33 pm
-
Lee–God help me, I have to agree w/ Person here, re Van Eeghen’s paper. May the gods forgive me!!
Mark et al.: “My opposition to corporations doesn’t spring from my views on torts. It springs from the simple fact that corporations are NOT of the marketplace, but are of the state.”But this argument could be used to say that marriage is not libertarian. After all, who cares whether there “would” be marriage still, absent the state–? the fact is, that “now”, the status of marriage “is” a creation of the state now. So it must be opposed.
September 26, 2006 at 3:05 pm
-
“But this argument could be used to say that marriage is not libertarian. After all, who cares whether there “would” be marriage still, absent the state–? the fact is, that “now”, the status of marriage “is” a creation of the state now. So it must be opposed.”
Uh, okay. How about this – nothing about voluntarily choosing your intimate or business partners should be illegal in a libertarian society. However, the legal ramifications attached to your decisions may or may not be consistent with a libertarian society. Hence –
“marriage” and “shareholder common ownership agreement” are never objectionable. Granting certain legal privileges to either arrangement, on the other hand, can be debated thoughtfully.
You gotta be careful agreeing with Person – you pick up his sloppy habit of focusing on red herrings. Next you’ll be complaining that everyone else is out to get you because they don’t understand your sloppy reasoning…
September 26, 2006 at 3:27 pm
-
quasibill:
Poor people can’t compensate, but are still held liable. Shareholders may or may not be factually able to compensate, they are just legally insulated from liability regardless of their ability to pay.
Okay, maybe I wasn’t clear. There are two separate issues at play here: 1) whether corporations unfairly expose others to risk they can’t cover, and 2) whether a person should be held liable for a specific tort. In my original post, I was addressing the general sentiment that (with respect to 1) ) corporations expose others to risk they can’t cover by noting that if they do, they do it to a far less extent than poor people, whom these ardent opponents of incorporation on the left (not surprisingly) give a free pass. You don’t necessarily endorse this point, so it may not apply to you.
Then, regarding 2), you’re claiming that as a shareholder, liability for (a certain set of) corporate torts inheres in my position. But my point here (and I believe Stephan’s) is that if I can achieve the exact same relationship with the corporation as currently stands, with some kind of bond (that I described above) — a bond which you agree does not put me on the hook for the corporation’s wrongdoing — then your claim just reduces to “corporations are bad because they use the wrong names for financial instruments in their dealings”. Not exactly a biting indictment.
Stephan said:the fact is, that “now”, the status of marriage “is” a creation of the state now. So it must be opposed.”
quasibill responded: Uh, okay. How about this – nothing about voluntarily choosing your intimate or business partners should be illegal in a libertarian society.
Hold on — you’ve already missed Stephan’s point. We all understand that you can go through an dileneate which parts of marriage are compatible with libertarianism and which aren’t. That wasn’t in dispute. The point is, by singling out an objectionable part of corporations, and using that to attack “corporations” as such (when so many parts of them are not objectionable), you’re making a statement exactly as useful and true as Stephan’s hypothetical statement about marriage.
And I’d drop the little jabs against me, if I were you.
September 26, 2006 at 6:13 pm
-
“a bond which you agree does not put me on the hook for the corporation’s wrongdoing — then your claim just reduces to “corporations are bad because they use the wrong names for financial instruments in their dealings”. Not exactly a biting indictment.”
Person(and Stephan for that matter), this is exactly right.
Wouldn’t Quasibill also have to concede that CONVERTIBLE bonds do not “put me on the hook for the corporation’s wrongdoing.
You can even have bonds that can be converted to stock and back again.
September 26, 2006 at 8:58 pm
-
To up the ante, can Stephan or any one (or any person ) explain why such a thing as a “corporation” would be necessary from a strictly commercial standpoint? I can’t see one and joke with clients all the time that sole proprietorship is the way to go — unless you want to defraud public, in which case a corporation is THE way to go.
Also, someone once referred me to a very interesting paper on how Amex was once a pass through liability corporation. (Don’t Leave Home Without It: Limited Liability and American Express by Mark I. Weinstein)
That’s right, it was publicly traded with the understanding that owners of shares could be hit with a big bill a la Lloyd’s in the 80′s. Amex was also monsterously profitable during this time and its shares were considered desireable. Interesting, eh? September 26, 2006 at 9:53 pm
-
A learned friend has suggested that I correct my spelling of monstrously and desirable. Done.
September 26, 2006 at 11:09 pm
-
Lee,
The reason why such a thing as a “corporation” would be necessary from a strictly commercial standpoint (in anarchy) is that it would facilitate faster and more efficient formation and accumulation of capital while at the same time accommodating the need for contractual agreements between property owners.
The corporation is a shorthand for a limited liability towards creditors, employees, clients, customers and whatever. It says basically if we are a limited company, and you agree to do business with us, you agree not to go after more than the worth of the assets of the company if you sue as a creditor, or as an unsatisfied customer. This could be accomplished in other ways, such as individual contracts but such an approach would be unnecessarily cumbersome and expensive. Limited corporations relieve groups of capitalists from having to pay for that particular administrative/legal overhead.
Obviously, capitalists will be much less likely to take equity positions in any given venture if the liability they take on for such an undertaking is unlimited. Any attempt at restricting contract making between property owners can only be deemed unlibertarian and aggressive. There can be no justification for disallowing market participants from coming up with innovations in contractual arrangements such as this. All that is required is proper notification and clarity of what a limited corporation means, and buyer beware.
September 27, 2006 at 2:04 am
-
Quasibill,
- I think that you’re on to something here about the way in which the law unevenly distributes vicarious liability across different forms of business organization. That is to say, the law holds the “owner” of a sole proprietorship vicariously liable for the tortious acts of his employees so long as they are committed in the scope of employment, whereas it does not hold corporate shareholders, who are thought to be the “owners” of corporations, liable for the same.
- This poses a real problem – the extent to which this differential treatment distorts the structure of production is unclear, but would seem to lead to different patterns of organization than would otherwise obtain. However, the problem of inconsistency may be resolved in one of two ways: either by eliminating the vicarious liability of the sole proprietor or by extending vicarious liability to the corporate shareholder. Which of these alternatives is appropriate depends upon whether or not the doctrine of Respondeat Superior is itself justifiable (if it is, it has not as of yet been satisfactorily justified).
- I am still trying to work through this and other issues pertaining to libertarian agency law (Randy Barnett’s piece on Agency Law got me started along the lines I am currently sketching out). I think, though, that Mr. Kinsella is absolutely correct that the default position has to be that an actor (and only that actor) is liable for the torts that he personally causes (i.e. there is neither immunity, nor collective guilt). Others (employers, parents, etc.) may be held jointly and severally liable for those same acts, but this “may” only becomes an “are” upon demonstration of the proper connection between the two persons (here, I would probably want to see some showing of complicity — this would perhaps extend from the clear case of ordering the tortious act to quietly condoning and profiting from an act which one has the power and right to control and thereby prevent).
- I think that even under agency law as it currently exists in Ango-American law, for a principal-agent relationship to exist at all, three requirements must be met: consent, benefit, and right of control. If the putative master has neither the power nor the right to control the agent’s actions, then no agency relationship exists. The question is, does a non-controlling shareholder in a publicly-traded corporation meet this basic control requirement? I think that’s a doubtful proposition.
- Also: Even if the requirements for a bare agency relationship are met, the doctrine of Respondeat Superior only applies in a certain type of agency relationship known as master-servant relationship. Beyond a mere right to control ends, the putative master must have the right to physically control and select the means employed by the putative servant to accomplish those ends. It seems quite obvious to me, that the limited voting rights that inhere in ownership of a share of common stock do not by a longshot empower a shareholder to wield such control (if one possessed a controlling interest, of course the situation might be very different).
- As for your response to the doubt Mr. Kinsella expressed in the bottum portion of his original post, it is my understanding that you are quite right about how the corporate form shields the shareholder from vicarious liability for torts (unless the shareholder used the corporation as a mere instrumentality or as an alter ego, so allowing for veil piercing); however, insofar as the shareholder is not vicariously, but directly responsible for committing harm, the corporate form does not shield him from liability therefor.
- Cheers,
Araglin
September 27, 2006 at 11:22 am
-
Briefly, my understanding is that corporations became somewhat popular when merchants would undertake one-shot ventures with a fixed terminus. Think of a ship sailing from London to India loaded with metals and expecting to return full of spices. At the conclusion of the venture, all investor/owners would receive a pro-rata share of the proceeds, minus costs. The corporation as such would end, and then another formed for yet another venture, etc.
As a business enterprise this made perfect sense. Each investor/owner had a pro-rata ownership interest that would be liquidated at the conclusion of the venture. He would invest knowing that his potential downside was the amount of investment, and his potential upside was whatever profits could be brought about by the traveling merchant manager and the intrepid ship captain.
It also neatly seperated liability according to the fairly commonsensical idea that if it’s captain and traveling merchant who will “act” while far far away, it shouldn’t be the shorebound investor/owners who pay for misdeeds of the traveling merchant or captain.
Prior to the advent of the corporation one had choice of lending money (no liability but limited upside) or being partners (big liability and potential big upside). Corporations made perfect sense and, indeed, allowed for the accumulation of larger sums of money allowing for “longer structures of production” in the form of ever-bigger ships and longer voyages, etc. (More spice spice, baby.)
The problem was that cunning conmen immediately saw the potential for making this otherwise harmless social fiction of a ‘corporation’ into a money-making machine. Let’s make the corporation immortal, they thought. It lives forever. Investor/owners give us money, we buy lots of assets, make the corporation look profitable, watch as ownership shares rise in value on the secondary market, and then rip everyone off! I can almost see the gleam in the eyes of our early railroad and shipping barons, et al.
On a more serious note, there is no a priori reason why corporations should be a more efficient or effective means of raising large sums of money for capital-intensive ventures. I believe many of our glorious capitalists of the past were quite capable of raising capital by other means, such as limited-life partnerships, hybrid loans with partial promise of share of profits, traditional bank loans, internal financing through cashflow generated by other ventures, etc.
It is, I think, a myth that the corporate form was necessary for anything, save making conmen rich. It’s like the myth of government — but if we don’t surrender our sovereign rights to the king/elected officials/fuhrer then anarchy will prevail. This is a lie. As is the claim that corporations ever were “necessary” for anything but fleecing the public.
Finally, as to liability, of course Stephan is right (as usual). If it is the act that causes the effect, we should follow the chain of action back to the actor. The path can be a twisted one (eg, Stephan tells me to shoot patent office clerk who denied his patent for Cajun Martini Blender), but the concept seems clear. Afterall, there can be but two basic categories, action and thought. Punishing the latter is rather unfair (think of difference between spouse denying you meatloaf because you said he/she looked fat in that outfit versus the denying you meatloaf because he/she thinks you thought he/she looks fat…ponder that). September 27, 2006 at 12:42 pm
-
Person:
“And I’d drop the little jabs against me, if I were you.”
Coming from the king of personal jabs (often pre-emptively), that’s rich.
“then your claim just reduces to “corporations are bad because they use the wrong names for financial instruments in their dealings”.”
No. I’m saying that if you hold an equity share, meaning you a) claim ownership of the res, and b) maintain a claim to profits from the res, essentially unlimited in an absolute sense by any contract term, you are not a mere creditor. Once again, we can play all sorts of games, calling a duck a frog, so long as we have an asterisk and all sorts of legalese afterwards, but if we want to ground this discussion in a meaningful way, we have to recognize there is a difference between claiming ownership and being a creditor. And if shareholders don’t own the assets of the corporation, who does?
“The point is, by singling out an objectionable part of corporations, and using that to attack “corporations” as such (when so many parts of them are not objectionable), you’re making a statement exactly as useful and true as Stephan’s hypothetical statement about marriage.”
And once again reading comprehension fails you. My point was merely that those who reflexively defend corporatins AS THEY CURRENTLY EXIST, are akin to those defending the entity that is state regulated marriage. I’ve noted that I agree with Stephan’s ultimate point – that causation is really the important question. My post was merely to point out that “fictitious personhood” as it currently exists, actually does not accomplish what Stephan thought it did.
Araglin,
good points. I agree that an argument can be made that liability for sole proprietors may be the area where there is a problem with current law from a libertarian standpoint. My default position, though, is that anything developed through hundreds of years of common law with respect to business practices is the default right answer, that must be shown to be wrong. In the same vein, I view any recent (100 years or so) statutory law in the same area very suspiciously, with an assumption that it is the result of some social engineer.
“Even if the requirements for a bare agency relationship are met, the doctrine of Respondeat Superior only applies in a certain type of agency relationship known as master-servant relationship.”
I tended to shy away from respondeat superior, because it’s actually somewhat different from the point I was trying to make, and I actually believe that RS isn’t entirely fundamentally sound. Under traditional agency law, an agent can have several types of authority, including “apparent”, and with that authority bind the principal by his acts. Now in terms of contracts, quite clearly those who understand corporations understand that agents are limited in their authority. But in the case of where the agent uses his apparent authority to commit a tort, traditionally the principal could be held liable for the tort.
To me, the question is whether the principal has acted responsibly with respect to how his property is utilized. RS, corporations, and even to a small extent agency law, all add confusing legalese that detracts from, instead of clarifying, this basic issue.
Note that this is different from being a creditor in that a creditor has a contractually defined absolute return. Any “loan” instrument that allows for an unlimited absolute return is not a loan, it’s a share in ownership. A loan is a temporary surrender of ownership of property, where as a share of a corporation is a surrender of the right of possession of property while retaining ultimate ownership.
“The question is, does a non-controlling shareholder in a publicly-traded corporation meet this basic control requirement?”
Where no shareholder has a controlling stake, who is the principal? Who owns the corporation? Not the managers, clearly – we refer to them as agents, of course to a fictitious person, but that’s the problem. A real person must actually be an owner somewhere along the chain. So the only logical place for ownership is shareholders.
So you challenge control. Okay, minority shareholders can’t control anything directly, but then again, who put themselves in that position? Where they no claim of control over something they claim to own? Should we reward them for such careless behavior with a blanket immunity? Or should we just treat them like any other owner of property owned commonly (joint tenants and tenants by the entireties also)?
In the end, as you note, the problem is that this differential legal treatment is not based on a reasoned foundation, and therefore distorts capital structure. I prefer levelling the playing field with the simple question, like Stephan in his original article, to “did D’s negligence cause the injury stated?” No need to drown in legalese about master/servant, corporate veils, etc. In the absence of that, I’ll take either shielding sole proprietors like shareholders, or exposing shareholders like sole proprietors. It’s more important in the big picture that the law treats owners equally.
September 27, 2006 at 2:46 pm
-
Quasibill: God help me, I tend to agree w/ Person here (except you are right about his jabs in many cases).
Person: “then your claim just reduces to “corporations are bad because they use the wrong names for financial instruments in their dealings”.”
QB: No. I’m saying that if you hold an equity share, meaning you a) claim ownership of the res, and b) maintain a claim to profits from the res, essentially unlimited in an absolute sense by any contract term, you are not a mere creditor.
The problem I have with this is that you are relying too heavily on terminology. What does it *mean* to “own the res”? Why is this relevant anyway? Because of what ownership itself means–which is the *right to control*. It makes perfect sense to focus on this, when trying to find causal responsibility for what someone else does directly. If I have some kind of signficant influence or control over the others’ actions, then yeah, maybe I’m implicated. But it’s because of the right to control–whatever you call it.
Once this is realized, then you see there are many forms of “right to control” which the law does not classify as ownership (e.g., a significant customer or creditor can pressure a company or even have contractual covenants); and many things the law calls ownership that have little right to control (the “naked owner” (owner of the residue or estate in reversion) of a piece of land that someone else has a life usufruct (life estate-life tenant) over has very little control of it). It is putting form over substance to fixate on the legal terminology used to describe certain relationships–especially the legal terms flowing from state positive law.
“I tended to shy away from respondeat superior, because it’s actually somewhat different from the point I was trying to make, and I actually believe that RS isn’t entirely fundamentally sound.”
Right–that’s why I said (as Gabb quoted me) that you have to first show RS is libertarian to have liability in the first place. The responsibilyt of the employer or the owner of the company-employer for the actions of the employee rests on RS.
“To me, the question is whether the principal has acted responsibly with respect to how his property is utilized.”
Maybe. But without RS, in order to hold the owner of property liable for torts committed by a third party using that property, you would have to say that loaning to someone is itself negligent, which is ridiculous. If I rent a car from Hertz and use it to ram into a crowd, why should Hertz be liable?
I believe many libertarians have some kind of bizarre, yet unstated and unjustified, assumption that Hertz should be. Why? Why? It needs to be shown, not just assumed.
“Note that this is different from being a creditor in that a creditor has a contractually defined absolute return. Any “loan” instrument that allows for an unlimited absolute return is not a loan, it’s a share in ownership.”
Nonsense. Or: it does not matter. You are trying to pigeonhole things as either being “officially” ownership, or “not” ownerhsip, and then making a decision based on this determination. Why not just focus on the underlying reality instead.
“Okay, minority shareholders can’t control anything directly, but then again, who put themselves in that position?”
But when you buy a share from another shareholder you don’t cause anyhting to happen. the company already exists; you don’t even give them money.
September 27, 2006 at 3:02 pm
-
Is there a form of libertarianism that allows for differences on issues like this? In other words, could one society allow corporations and another not and both be considered equally consistent under libertarianism?
The reason I ask is that people have two ways of thinking about law: 1) One groups says that nothing is permitted except what is in the law. Europeans tend to lean this way. 2) Another group says everything is permitted except what the law forbids, which is more American.
It seems to me that the discussion above tends toward #1. Does a libertarian group that follows #2 exist?
September 27, 2006 at 3:24 pm
-
“Because of what ownership itself means–which is the *right to control*. ”
Yes, a form of property right. Hence, it describes a person as well. Who owns the property rights in corporate property? Who can assign the right to possess, or control? As I’ve noted, it can’t be the managers, as we automatically refer to them as agents. Agents of who? Well, the fictitious person, of course! So a fictitious person owns property? hello, State, welcome to my house…
“right to control” which the law does not classify as ownership (e.g., a significant customer or creditor can pressure a company or even have contractual covenants”
Are you seriously arguing that a customer has a property right in the property of a seller? It’s the difference between “right” and “influence”. Leftists make that mistake all the time – I expected more from you. The customer can influence the seller by offering enough money to encourage the seller to agree to a term. He has no property right until the seller transfers it.
“If I rent a car from Hertz and use it to ram into a crowd, why should Hertz be liable? ”
Funny you used this example, as I was thinking along similar lines when I made my argument. Here’s my re-statement:
QB is locking his car door as W, the town drunk approaches. W, reeking of alcohol and somewhat twitchy with white powder around his nose, asks QB for the keys to his car so he can pick up his friend at the airport. If QB gives W the keys to the car, can QB be held liable for W’s act in driving through the line of schoolchildren at the next intersection?
Does your answer change if QB first performs the magical incantations, calls himself QB taxicabs, Inc., grants equal shares to his next door neighbors, and then signs W to an employment agreement to be the director of QB taxicabs, with full management authority, before giving W the keys to the car (which of course, QB has assigned to the corporation)?
“But when you buy a share from another shareholder you don’t cause anyhting to happen. the company already exists; you don’t even give them money. ”
So? When I buy the dam on the river upstream, I don’t cause anything to happen – it already exists, and I don’t add any capital to the dam. However, I AM now owner of it, and CAN be held liable for a subsequent breach that causes damage down stream.
It’s really quite amazing to see you make Marxist arguments about property ownership. That it’s just some metaphorical construct, that abstractions can have rights, etc. Property rights are held by someone or someones in common to any owned property. Until you define who owns the property, it must be unowned. Who, by your tortured definitions, owns the corporate property, if not shareholders?
September 27, 2006 at 3:42 pm
-
Somewhat bill:
“right to control” which the law does not classify as ownership (e.g., a significant customer or creditor can pressure a company or even have contractual covenants”
Are you seriously arguing that a customer has a property right in the property of a seller?
Depends. They can–they can have contractual guarantees that force the seller to do certain things or not, w/ their own property. Is this not a form of co-ownership? It’s divided right to control. Same w/ creditors.
It’s the difference between “right” and “influence”. Leftists make that mistake all the time – I expected more from you.
But if I were exploring a theory of ownership, maybe so. The issue is *causation*. For that, we look at relevant factors. One of them is influence or control. Owenrship is relevant *only* because and to the extent it means control. In my view.
The customer can influence the seller by offering enough money to encourage the seller to agree to a term. He has no property right until the seller transfers it.
First, why does there have to be an ownership-based influence for it to matter for responsibility? If a wife pays a hit-man to kill her husband, she is responsible not b/c she owns the gun used or the hit-man. But beause of her role–her influence, her causal role. I discuss the importance of causation here: http://mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf/qjae7_4_7.pdf
Or what if she seduces her boyfriend or otherwise persuades him to kill her husband? She’s still liable (IMO).
Second–the customer can have property rights–there might be a contract having many obligations on waht the seller does with his property.
QB is locking his car door as W, the town drunk approaches. W, reeking of alcohol and somewhat twitchy with white powder around his nose, asks QB for the keys to his car so he can pick up his friend at the airport. If QB gives W the keys to the car, can QB be held liable for W’s act in driving through the line of schoolchildren at the next intersection?
Maybe–but you changed the context. Here QB is more involved. It’s like handing a gun to someone who is obviously likely to immediatley use it to go on a shooting rampage, and selling one to a hunter.
It’s really quite amazing to see you make Marxist arguments about property ownership. That it’s just some metaphorical construct, that abstractions can have rights, etc.
It’s not Marxist to say property means the right to control. It’s not Marxist to believe responsibility for others’ actions requires a coherent theory of causation; and that in order to prove such causation, “ownership” might be relevant primarily if and to the extent the ownerhsip implies some kind of relevant control; and that if so, other types of control or influence might also be relevant for a causal analysis.
Property rights are held by someone or someones in common to any owned property. Until you define who owns the property, it must be unowned. Who, by your tortured definitions, owns the corporate property, if not shareholders?
Why do you keep assuming A is liable for any tort commited by a third party who is using A’s property? This is an assertion that needs a justification.
September 27, 2006 at 4:13 pm
-
The problem here is in assuming that ownership of any particular asset must be unitary. It’s not. When a potential share-holder pays in capital to the corporation, he receives in return certain contractual rights: (1) to receive a pro rata share of any declared dividends; (2) to receive a pro rata share of assets minus liabilities upon liquidiation; and (3) the right to vote in certain situations. These contract rights (to the extent that they are enforceable) rest upon the parceling out of the various constituent parts of ownership among the parties of the corporate assets. If one has an enforceable right to insist that certain actions be/not be taken with certain property, under libertarian theory, that has to be because one or more of the “sticks” in the property “bundle” has passed into his hands. An asset isn’t unowned merely because no one possesses each and every one of the ownership rights.
Hope this finds all of you well,
Araglin September 27, 2006 at 7:04 pm
-
“They can–they can have contractual guarantees that force the seller to do certain things or not, w/ their own property.”
At which point, the seller has sold that property right to the customer. But he did, in fact sell it. That right existed before he entered into the contract.
“he issue is *causation*. For that, we look at relevant factors. One of them is influence or control. Owenrship is relevant *only* because and to the extent it means control.”
I actually agree. The problem is you are arbitrarily ending the chain at a given point. Noone forced the shareholder to enter into the agreement he did. He did, in fact, have absolute control of the property he exchanged for the share, and in fact, had every right in the world to demand more control in return. The fact that he intentionally tries to shirk responsibility for how his newly acquired property is then used doesn’t exactly make him automatically blameless for how it is used, in my view. He can be seen as contributing to the action by supplying the necessary means. Again, you and your newfound soulmate are fighting a bit of a strawman – I am not arguing for automatice liability. I’m merely arguing against automatic immunity.
“Or what if she seduces her boyfriend or otherwise persuades him to kill her husband? She’s still liable (IMO).”
Exactly. Or how about the situation where the teacher seduces a student, provides him a gun, and then blithely mentions that she can’t continue the relationship as long as her husband is alive? She has no control over what the student then does, and she hasn’t exercised any direct control over him, but she can still be found liable (IMO). Of course, if she incorporated herself and merely hired the student as a director and gave the equivalent information (here’s a nuclear plant, but unless we can find a cheap way to dispose of the waste so I can make a profit, I’ll have to fire you), current law saws – immunity! Wonderful, ain’t it?
“Here QB is more involved. It’s like handing a gun to someone who is obviously likely to immediatley use it to go on a shooting rampage, and selling one to a hunter.”
I see no change of context. You were claiming that there could never be liability for merely lending property to another. I showed that quite clearly there is an argument that there can be such liability. Shareholders voting in a CEO with a record of putting profits ahead of any concern for third parties are perfectly analogous – if the director then proceeds to violate 3rd party rights in pursuit of higher profits, can you honestly say that the shareholders had no causal connection?
What was the referrent to my “marxist” comment was your intimation that there is no real owner of corporate property – that an abstraction (such as “the proletariat” or a fictitious person) had property rights. I say, some real, living, individual has the property rights, individually or common with other real, living individuals. They do, in fact, delegate these rights when they make contracts. And, in fact, they can arguable be held liable for delegating those rights in a non-responsible manner.
“Why do you keep assuming A is liable for any tort commited by a third party who is using A’s property? This is an assertion that needs a justification.”
See above comment regarding the Ray Bolger you keep bringing to the table.
Araglin,
“The problem here is in assuming that ownership of any particular asset must be unitary.”
I think the only people assuming this are Kinsella et al. I’m merely saying that each right exists, and that in most pertinent situations, it originated as unitary ownership rights, either in an individual or in a group. The original unitary owner then delegated or sold some rights to others. These are, in fact, actions. It doesn’t just happen magically. Humans actually act to accomplish the transfer. The manner in which this transfer occurs *may* give rise to liability on the part of the transferor. NOthing more, nothing less.
September 27, 2006 at 10:18 pm
-
pseudo-bill:
“he issue is *causation*. For that, we look at relevant factors. One of them is influence or control. Owenrship is relevant *only* because and to the extent it means control.”
I actually agree. The problem is you are arbitrarily ending the chain at a given point. Noone forced the shareholder to enter into the agreement he did. He did, in fact, have absolute control of the property he exchanged for the share, and in fact, had every right in the world to demand more control in return. The fact that he intentionally tries to shirk responsibility for how his newly acquired property is then used doesn’t exactly make him automatically blameless for how it is used, in my view. He can be seen as contributing to the action by supplying the necessary means. Again, you and your newfound soulmate are fighting a bit of a strawman – I am not arguing for automatice liability. I’m merely arguing against automatic immunity.
No, I’m saying it could be either way too. Some shareholders could clearly be liable. For their particualr actions or role.
I simply say taht as a general matter, someone is responsible for another’s direct actions only if you can establish a sufficient causal link. Now, if you think *merely owning shares* in the company that pays money to someone to do something (an “employee”) is necessarily liable for any tort committed by that employee, I simply think it needs to be established. The burden is on you; and if you think it’s “obvious” or “obviously followS” from the fact that he’s a shareholder–it doesn’t. You have the burden. I don’t see how you can satisfy it but you are welcome to try.
That brings up another issue: “employee” is also an artifical concept; economically, waht’s teh difference between paying an independent contractor, or an “employee,” to do a task for you? Or even outsourcing something to another company?
I think the problem is some people have a general hostility to corporatism either b/c they have a left-libertarian aspect, or a paleo-agrarian one, or b/c they dislike the intertwining of global capitalism with government. So they come up with the limited liability complaint. But it’s not set in any carefully articulated, coherent theory of responsibilty.
I mean, let’s hear it: in a private joint stock company in your version of libertopia, what *exactly* is your theory of what liability shareholders should have? Are you saying they should have unlimited liability, for … what? any actions performed… by whom? By “employees’ of the company? or only by employees, performed in the couse of their employment? What about outsourced tasks done by “other” companies? what about the actions of “independent” contractors? Does the action have to be done “with” “property” owned by the shareholders/company? Or does merely being paid by the company implicate the company?
SEe, not only do you guys fail to set forth a careful theory of resonsibility and causation, you fail to even specify *what* you are trying to justify. I believe you need to carefully show what liability you think shareholders *should* have (that the law is currently somehow immunizing them from), and also what is the *justification* for this theory.
Or how about the situation where the teacher seduces a student, provides him a gun, and then blithely mentions that she can’t continue the relationship as long as her husband is alive? She has no control over what the student then does, and she hasn’t exercised any direct control over him, but she can still be found liable (IMO). Of course, if she incorporated herself and merely hired the student as a director and gave the equivalent information (here’s a nuclear plant, but unless we can find a cheap way to dispose of the waste so I can make a profit, I’ll have to fire you), current law saws -immunity!
I am not so sure you are right. But if so, that part is not justifiable. I have pointed out repeatedly that if someone is causally responsible, fine. In this case, it’s easy to make the case.
But notice: she is not responsible *merely because she is a shareholder*, but because, as yo uset up the hypo, she was orchestrating the whole thing.
This example does NOT show that a *mere* shareholder of a company is necessarily responsible for all torts committed by individuals the company pays to do things.
I see no change of context. You were claiming that there could never be liability for merely lending property to another.
Did I? I believe I was pointing out that if you say a shareholder is necessarily liable, it must be based on *something*. It has to be because he gave money to, or has control over, the company. In the former case, if you base it on this–then you would implicate all lenders too. Surely we don’t want this.
This dos not imply no lender could be liable. I can conceive of situations where they would. Where they pressure the company into committing a crime, etc.
Shareholders voting in a CEO with a record of putting profits ahead of any concern for third parties are perfectly analogous
Perhaps–but that is not merely because they are sharehodlers–it’s b/c of particualrthings they did in this case–and how would this theory implicate those who voted against the CEO, or who didn’t vote (anyway shareholders elect the directors, who hire the CEO).
– if the director then proceeds to violate 3rd party rights in pursuit of higher profits, can you honestly say that the shareholders had no causal connection?
Of course in some cases this can be shown. Sure, why not? I just say it’s not automatic.
What was the referrent to my “marxist” comment was your intimation that there is no real owner of corporate property
Of course it has an owner. Or owners. It’s divided; it does not rest all in the hands of shareholders (or not necessarily). As I pointed out: can the shareholders use the corporate jet? No. CAn the company sell all its assets? No, not if the bank has covenants or liens preventing it. Etc. Ownership–the right to control–is spread among many entities. Deal with it.
See above comment regarding the Ray Bolger you keep bringing to the table.
What?
“The problem here is in assuming that ownership of any particular asset must be unitary.”
I think the only people assuming this are Kinsella et al.
Im not assuming this. The opposite, if anything.
September 28, 2006 at 12:17 am
-
quasibill: are you going to address the issue of convertible bonds that Kristian brought up or the variable bonds that I brought up?
September 28, 2006 at 7:43 am
-
Stephan,
Let’s step back and see if you agree with my summary so far, and see what you disagree with:
uncontested:
1. sole proprietorships and corporations are treated differently with respect to liability for employee actions. Sole proprietors have respondeat superior, while shareholders have limited liability.
2. Limited liability has no connection to the concept of causation. Piercing the corporate veil is not based on determining whether there was control or causation, rather it merely attempts to determine if the shareholder didn’t respect the corporate identity.
3. Respondeat superior may or may not be justified as to sole proprietors (and therefore corporations as well) – but if you believe it isn’t, RS should be changed, instead of granting artificial privileges to shareholders in corporations. There is no valid reason to distinguish between the two forms of ownership in this respect. What holds for one as a general rule should hold for the other.
Any problems with that?
(Ray Bolger had an important role in the Wizard of Oz)
All of which leads us to:
“I believe I was pointing out that if you say a shareholder is necessarily liable”
Strawman – I never, not once, claimed automatic liability. In fact, I have, from the beginning, only argued AGAINST automatic immunity, which is what current corporate law provides. You keep trying to rotate the positions, but it doesn’t work. YOU are defending an absolute position. I’m merely arguing that corporations, as they exist, posess privileges that they wouldn’t absent the state.
“Perhaps–but that is not merely because they are sharehodlers–it’s b/c of particualrthings they did in this case–and how would this theory implicate those who voted against the CEO, or who didn’t vote (anyway shareholders elect the directors, who hire the CEO).”
Exactly. And under current law, none of this is considered. You can only get this far if you first jump through the hoops of “piercing the corporate veil.”
“Of course it has an owner. Or owners. It’s divided; it does not rest all in the hands of shareholders (or not necessarily). As I pointed out: can the shareholders use the corporate jet? No. CAn the company sell all its assets? No, not if the bank has covenants or liens preventing it. Etc. Ownership–the right to control–is spread among many entities. Deal with it.”
I have dealt with it. You can’t seem to get past the point that you are defending an entity, as it currently exists, that doesn’t. As in this statement:
“I am not so sure you are right.”
After you spent your first several paragraphs excoriating leftist and agrarians for their supposed inability to present a coherent defense of their vision, you come up with that? You’re going to the mat to defend corporations as they exist based on that? Okay…
Let’s put out there again, nice and slowly –
Shareholders currently have no liability for how they use their share rights, unless they fail to respect the corporate identity. You consistently claim that this is just peachy in your world, while out the other side of your mouth claiming that the only issue should be causation (“Of course in some cases this can be shown. Sure, why not? I just say it’s not automatic.”) Surprise! – I agree with the second statement (“I am not arguing for automatice liability. I’m merely arguing against automatic immunity.”) (nice spelling on my part, BTW). Just not the first. In that vein, as I’ve already clearly stated above, both RS and limited liability serve only to confuse the question.
Person –
Answered several times. In fact, just re-read the exchange between NSK and myself, and it is addressed at least 3 times over. In fact, I have clearly stated several times what my standard would be (hint, that helps other people actually determine what you mean when you argue – I know someone who fails to do this repeatedly in the IP context…)
September 28, 2006 at 8:34 am
-
quasibill: No, you did not address convertible or variable bonds. You may have given a standard, but you never applied it to those cases. And considering how hard your position is to follow, no, you can’t count that as an explanation. Earlier in the thread you said, essentially, “managers ‘are considered’ agents, so obviously they can’t be owners” — that’s right, because of how economists describe the principle-agent problem, that determines the relationships between the actors. So, no, it’s a bit hard to get answers out of you. Try to explain how convertible bonds and variable bonds fit into your narrow framework.
September 28, 2006 at 11:01 am
-
Not-quite-bill:
1. sole proprietorships and corporations are treated differently with respect to liability for employee actions. Sole proprietors have respondeat superior, while shareholders have limited liability.
I think I see what you’re trying to get at here. You see a sole proprietor as responsible for employees’ torts; yet you think there is an artificial exemption for “joint owners”. If they just “stand in the shoes” of a sole proprietor, why aren’t they collectively liable?
But a sole proprietor is liable because he directs the actions of the negligent employee, and actually runs the company–sets policies, controls is, manages it. In a joint stock company, the shareholders don’t do any of this. They elect the board, which appoints managers. In my view, the managers are more analogous to the sole proprietor than the shareholders are.
Let me also ask you: have you read Robert Hessen’s by-now classic work on this, In Defense of the Corporation? It’s a very thorough, learned defense, based on libertarian principles. I really think anyone wanting to weigh in on this needs to be familiar with this pioneering work. He handles tons of these kinds of objections.
Before proceeding further, let me list here some good resources on this that really should be studied by anyone seriously interested in this issue:
- my blogposts, In Defense of the Corporation and Legitimizing the Corporation
- The NRA Gets It Wrong (section “Corporations and the state”), by Sheldon Richman, Freedom Daily
- The Theory of the
Corporation, by Norman Barry, Ideas on Liberty - Killing Corporations:
The movement to revoke corporate charters has gotten its history confused, by Jesse Walker, Reason - Corporations and Rights: On Treating Corporate People Justly, by Roger Pilon
- summary of the Pilon article in Literature of Liberty
Richman notes:
What about torts, or actions that harm people who are not parties to any contract? (We’re primarily concerned with unintentional torts here.) Partners in an unincorporated firm can personally be sued by someone, say injured by a company vehicle, but not so a shareholder. This seems to confirm that corporate status is a privilege.
Hessen explains that in England long ago the “principle of vicarious liability” was established, holding that a master was liable for the torts of his servant. This was reasonable because the master hired, trained, and supervised the servant. Later the same principle, reasonably, was “extended to sole proprietorships and general partners.” However, he says, it doesn’t follow that it should be applied to all holders of corporate stock. Hessen writes,
Vicarious liability should only apply to those shareholders who play an active role in managing an enterprise or in selecting and supervising its employees and agents. The tort liability of inactive shareholders should be the same as that of limited partners — that is, limited to the amount invested — and for the same reason; namely, inactive shareholders and limited partners contribute capital but do not participate actively in management and control.
I had forgotten this but must have absorbed it when I read Hessen long ago. Hessen here is making the same basic causation point I have made here: that vicarious liability must be relied on to hold someone liable for the servant’s actions–and in the case of a sole proprietorship, it is reasonable to do so because the proprietor/master is hiring, training, supervising the servant/employee. But in the case of a joint stock company, the same idea applies only to those sharehlolders who “play an active role in managing an enterprise or in selecting and supervising its employees and agents”.
This makes sense to me. Merely being a shareholder is not sufficient. It’s having control. I believe most of the corporation opponents have some view that inherently connects liability to property. I think this is confused and wrong. Liability flows from one’s actions–from control–from causing the harm to occur.
2. Limited liability has no connection to the concept of causation. Piercing the corporate veil is not based on determining whether there was control or causation, rather it merely attempts to determine if the shareholder didn’t respect the corporate identity.
Look. The point is this. Le’ts not stray. Libertarian critics of the corporation base this criticism on certain features, namely limited liability. The question is: in a private society, with no state privilege, could private actors form the basically same type of arrangement that had the features you guys complain about. We have shown that contractual limited liability is no problem. What about torts? See above.
3. Respondeat superior may or may not be justified as to sole proprietors (and therefore corporations as well) – but if you believe it isn’t, RS should be changed, instead of granting artificial privileges to shareholders in corporations. There is no valid reason to distinguish between the two forms of ownership in this respect. What holds for one as a general rule should hold for the other.
See Hessen’s comments above re vicarious liability. I think this is a sound analysis.
Bottom line: Hessen solved all this back in the 1970s. Critics usually ignorant of what has gone before keep reinventing the same critiques, that have already been addressed.
“I believe I was pointing out that if you say a shareholder is necessarily liable”
Strawman – I never, not once, claimed automatic liability. In fact, I have, from the beginning, only argued AGAINST automatic immunity, which is what current corporate law provides.
Does it? If an employee–say a truck driver of FedEx–is also a shareholder, and negligently runs over someone, does his status as a shareholder immunize him? Nope.
You keep trying to rotate the positions, but it doesn’t work. YOU are defending an absolute position. I’m merely arguing that corporations, as they exist, posess privileges that they wouldn’t absent the state.
Shareholders *per se* do not seem to exert enough control to be liable vicariously. The shareholders that do exert enough control, ought to be liable.
“Perhaps–but that is not merely because they are sharehodlers–it’s b/c of particualrthings they did in this case–and how would this theory implicate those who voted against the CEO, or who didn’t vote (anyway shareholders elect the directors, who hire the CEO).”
Exactly. And under current law, none of this is considered. You can only get this far if you first jump through the hoops of “piercing the corporate veil.”
But I am not defending this aspect of corporations. So long as people would be free in private society to (a) limit shareholder’s contractual liability for debts of the corporation; and (b) not be held to be automatically responsible vicariously for actions of the company’s employees merely becuase they are shareholders, then we have the seed of a simalcrum of a corporation.
You can’t seem to get past the point that you are defending an entity, as it currently exists, that doesn’t.
You seem to not be able to get past the convenient use of legal fictions. It’s just a way of conceptually dealing wtih something. It’s not like it hast o have a platonic essence.
Shareholders currently have no liability for how they use their share rights, unless they fail to respect the corporate identity. You consistently claim that this is just peachy in your world,
No. What i claim is that in a free society I see no problem with shareholders having a form of limited liability, even for torts, becuase being a shareholder does not in and of itself mean you are necessarily actively controlling what the tortfeasors do. I also see no problem holding a particular shareolders–or director, or manager, or lender, or customer, or vendor, or employee, or wife of the CEO–liable vicariously for the acts of a particular employee, if it can be shown that there is sufficient causal connection. I only maintain that merely being a shareholder is not sufficient. The libertarian critics of the corporation implicitly rest their critique on the idea that *merely* being an “owner” is sufficient. that is what i deny. ARe you now retracting this? Note that Gabb, above, does imply this.
In any event–as Hessen also points out:
Regardless of one’s view about limited liability for torts, the whole issue is irrelevant to giant corporations, which either carry substantial liability insurance or possess sizeable net assets from which claims can be paid.
September 28, 2006 at 11:31 am
-
Let’s be clear, certain “libertarian critics” of the corporation don’t focus on limited liability as much as they focus on how useless and meaningless the corporate form is. The mistake made by many (I have yet to digest 126 pages of Pilon’s thinking on this), is that they assume the corporate form serves a legitimate purpose. It doesn’t, it can’t and it never has (contrary to popular myth — similar to the myths of “rights granted to us by constitution” and “government is necessary to secure our rights, build roads, provide justice, secure patent rights,” bla bla). That’s the illusion we need to dispense with, and then we can lollgag around on issues of liability in a world of disjointed actions and perfect freedom.
September 28, 2006 at 11:35 am
-
Person –
forgive me if I fail to respond to your posts – its clear we have a communication problem. You have, in the past, claimed to have clearly refuted certain arguments. I see your alleged refutations, and they are as clear as mud to me. The opposite appears to be true as well. What to me is a clear answer to your point, you don’t understand. We seem to speak different languages. I gain nothing from our exchanges, and its clear my posts aren’t useful to you. In the end, we degenerate to name calling, which is not beneficial to either of our positions.
Stephan,
“But a sole proprietor is liable because he directs the actions of the negligent employee, and actually runs the company–sets policies, controls is, manages it.”
But that is not all. He is also the ultimate owner, who has the right to decide that someone else will run the company. For example, the common practice of franchisees to hire a location manager, who in actuality is responsible for all day to day operation. But the manager ultimately derives his authority from the owner, who has non-permanently delegated it to him. This delegation is, in itself, an act that has consequences in the world. For this act, the sole proprietor can be held responsible, including a situation where the sole proprietor hired a dangerous manager because that manager was likely to yield higher profits.
As I’ve noted, the shareholder’s decision to hire a director is, in fact, absolutely immune as long as they follow some statutorily defined rituals. They ARE the ultimate owner involved, and they ARE the one(s) that delegate the right to control to the managers. This delegation IS an action for which liability can possibly accrue, under a libertarian theory. Under current law, it can’t, unless the shareholder disregards a fictitious concept.
I have at some time or another, read all of those sources, although, like you, I don’t have handy recall to all of the points contained therein.
As for Hessen, I don’t agree entirely with his analysis of vicarious liability with respect to inactive shareholders. To the extent that they are inactive by legal inability, his analysis is fine. To the extent they have the right to be inactive, but fail to exercise that right, they can be held liable for their failure to use their right in a responsible manner. Other than that, his analysis seems to agree with everything else we seem to have agreed upon.
“Does it? If an employee–say a truck driver of FedEx–is also a shareholder, and negligently runs over someone, does his status as a shareholder immunize him? Nope.”
Strawman. He is not liable in his identity as a shareholder, he is liable in his identity as an employee. Again, the point is that to the extent he has exercised a right that can be linked in the causal chain to the harm caused, there is an argument that he should be liable. Current corporate law arbitrarily protects shareholders from the possible consequences of their actions.
“So long as people would be free in private society to (a) limit shareholder’s contractual liability for debts of the corporation; and (b) not be held to be automatically responsible vicariously for actions of the company’s employees merely becuase they are shareholders, then we have the seed of a simalcrum of a corporation.”
Well, I’d limit (a) to “contractual debts” in the sense that at least one *real* person would have to be responsible for its tortious debts – that would be a matter of contract (indemnity, etc.) between the shareholders, but they could not extinguish the rights of non-parties to their contract.
And 2nd, “simalcum” is a good description. It is not, in fact, what we currently have. The extent of the difference in practice is impossible to predict with certainty.
“You seem to not be able to get past the convenient use of legal fictions”
Maybe because legal fictions are a front for defrauding the less sophisticated. Look, I have no problem (legally) with hucksters swindling the unsophisticated out of their money, but I prefer that they are actually forced to spell it out up front, during dickering. Can you honestly argue that a person who doesn’t understand the meaning of “inc.” consented to limited contractual liability? To me, you only can by using arguments akin to you consenting to the current Constitution.
“The libertarian critics of the corporation implicitly rest their critique on the idea that *merely* being an “owner” is sufficient. that is what i deny. ARe you now retracting this?”
Not totally. I think you are too glib as to the concept of who delegates the rights of control, but beyond that, I think we agree.
As far as Gabb’s critique, I agree with much of his criticism of the cultural effects, but I don’t trace the problem to corporations per se, but to the “public” markets as established by states as well as the central banks. “Close” corporations absent Fed currency manipulations, would, in fact, probably not have created so many cultural negatives.
September 28, 2006 at 11:55 am
-
Lee:
Let’s be clear, certain “libertarian critics” of the corporation don’t focus on limited liability as much as they focus on how useless and meaningless the corporate form is. The mistake made by many (I have yet to digest 126 pages of Pilon’s thinking on this), is that they assume the corporate form serves a legitimate purpose. It doesn’t, it can’t and it never has (contrary to popular myth — similar to the myths of “rights granted to us by constitution” and “government is necessary to secure our rights, build roads, provide justice, secure patent rights,” bla bla). That’s the illusion we need to dispense with, and then we can lollgag around on issues of liability in a world of disjointed actions and perfect freedom.
What is the purpose of arguing that a corporation has no purpose? What is the relevance? Even if this were right, it has nothing to do with libertarianism.
Bit-of-Bill:
“But a sole proprietor is liable because he directs the actions of the negligent employee, and actually runs the company–sets policies, controls is, manages it.”
But that is not all. He is also the ultimate owner, who has the right to decide that someone else will run the company.
for some reason you guys see some relevance in being able to Name that sommeone is the Ultimate Owner. I think you’re putting the cart befor the horse; you are failing to provide an *argument* for why mere ownerhsip interests give rise to *vicarious liability*.
For example, the common practice of franchisees to hire a location manager, who in actuality is responsible for all day to day operation. But the manager ultimately derives his authority from the owner, who has non-permanently delegated it to him. This delegation is, in itself, an act that has consequences in the world. For this act, the sole proprietor can be held responsible, including a situation where the sole proprietor hired a dangerous manager because that manager was likely to yield higher profits.
I believe the world has nuances. Context and facts matter. Not all cases are alike. I think there is a difference between what a sole proprietor does and what a shareholder does. Apparently you do not. I think the manager is more analogous to a sole proprietor. They have similar control in making policy, hiring and directing employees. You think the shareholder and proprietor have more in common–becuase they are both “owners”. I focus on control and causation as elements of what determins “vicarious” responsibility. I have given reasons why (in my paper on Causation). You by contrast seem to focus on the Officail Deeming that someone is an Ultimate Owner. I have yet to see a reason given for connecting Ownership with vicarious liability.
As I’ve noted, the shareholder’s decision to hire a director is, in fact, absolutely immune as long as they follow some statutorily defined rituals.
I don’t agree that they should be. I can conceive of some cases where there might be liability. Perhaps.
They ARE the ultimate owner involved,
So??
and they ARE the one(s) that delegate the right to control to the managers.
No, they select the Board of Directors. The Board hires managers. Managers then supervise employees or contractors.
This delegation IS an action for which liability can possibly accrue, under a libertarian theory. Under current law, it can’t, unless the shareholder disregards a fictitious concept.
to the extent this is true, I would agree, that would not be teh case under libertarian law. But this is minor.
“Does it? If an employee–say a truck driver of FedEx–is also a shareholder, and negligently runs over someone, does his status as a shareholder immunize him? Nope.”
Strawman. He is not liable in his identity as a shareholder, he is liable in his identity as an employee.
It’s not a strawman; I’m trying to make sure the description you are resting your critique upon is accurate.
Again, the point is that to the extent he has exercised a right that can be linked in the causal chain to the harm caused, there is an argument that he should be liable.
Yes. I just say mere ownership is not enough to show this. Do. You. Agree?
“So long as people would be free in private society to (a) limit shareholder’s contractual liability for debts of the corporation; and (b) not be held to be automatically responsible vicariously for actions of the company’s employees merely becuase they are shareholders, then we have the seed of a simalcrum of a corporation.”
Well, I’d limit (a) to “contractual debts” in the sense that at least one *real* person would have to be responsible for its tortious debts – that would be a matter of contract (indemnity, etc.) between the shareholders, but they could not extinguish the rights of non-parties to their contract.
sure, by (a) I am refering to contractually acuiqred obligtions wtih third parties. They are on notice they can only pursue the assets of the company, not the shareholders individually.
And 2nd, “simalcum” is a good description. It is not, in fact, what we currently have. The extent of the difference in practice is impossible to predict with certainty.
Yes but you people are critiquing features we say are not problematic about corporations. I find in fact the whole obsession w/ corporations to be crankish and kind of leftist or something.
Maybe because legal fictions are a front for defrauding the less sophisticated.
Oh. Now it’s an argument for fraud. Sheesh.
Can you honestly argue that a person who doesn’t understand the meaning of “inc.” consented to limited contractual liability?
? I don’t frankly care. If people parties to an agreement don’t take the time to specify it carefully enough, they are to blame. If enough people are harmed by the wrong legal presumption, then practices will change.
As far as Gabb’s critique, I agree with much of his criticism of the cultural effects,
Sure. But I find that a-libertarian. Interesting, but irrelevant.
September 28, 2006 at 12:44 pm
-
“I think you’re putting the cart befor the horse; you are failing to provide an *argument* for why mere ownerhsip interests give rise to *vicarious liability*.”
No, you put the cart before the horse, as you must determine who is delegating a power before you can determine whether there can be vicarious liability. No person who does not have superior rights to the property can be found to be vicariously liable. Quite simple, no? Then, you move on to whether the delegation was a responsible use of that property right. Apparently it’s okay to just assume someone might have a property right and then begin the vicarious liability analysis. I say it flows the other direction.
And that’s important, because you need to know where the corporate manager’s authority comes from. It’s not an inherent right – in most cases, his powers are revokable at will by someone else. Who might that someone else be? Were they responsible in their delegation to that manager in the first place? Were they responsible in not revoking the delegation earlier?
You seem to be arguing that these questions aren’t relevant, because you don’t like identifying who actually owns the property rights at stake. I say that that is the first question that must be answered.
“I believe the world has nuances. Context and facts matter. Not all cases are alike”
I agree. Which is why blanket immunities (and for that matter, blanket liabilities) given to distinct classes are *always* problematic.
“I think the manager is more analogous to a sole proprietor. They have similar control in making policy, hiring and directing employees. You think the shareholder and proprietor have more in common–becuase they are both “owners”. I focus on control and causation as elements of what determins “vicarious” responsibility. I have given reasons why (in my paper on Causation). You by contrast seem to focus on the Officail Deeming that someone is an Ultimate Owner. I have yet to see a reason given for connecting Ownership with vicarious liability.”
You’re skipping right over it. By what right does the corporate manager have control? By what right does the sole proprietor have control? Hint – corporate managers don’t have a “right” at all, but a “power under authority”, just like the day to day manager under a sole proprietor does. This is where you are constantly returning to a Marxist conception of property rights being held by some abstract entity. The entity does not exist. It is in fact composed of individuals who must act for it to have any ability to actually act.
“But this is minor.”
Ah, well there it is. You value it to be minor, whereas I see it as non-trivial. Can we resolve this conflict? Well, you, as a Randroid type, probably think so. We’ll just have to agree to disagree on your valuation. But it’s nice to finally have the concession.
“Yes. I just say mere ownership is not enough to show this. Do. You. Agree?”
I. am. saying. that. mere. ownership. is. enough. to. ask. the. question. whether. the. owner. delegated. his. property. rights. in. a. responsible. manner. The rest of the analysis flows from there. If the owner wasn’t negligent (or worse) in this decision to delegate, and that is the only link in the causal chain to the owner – no.liability.
“Yes but you people ”
Can I pick up anything written by Rand and state that “you people” argue [x]? Please, stop with the collectivism. I’ve made my individual argument. Don’t ask me to defend positions I have not taken, and I’ll do the same for you.
“Oh. Now it’s an argument for fraud. Sheesh”
Read carefully, and you’ll note that I’ve declined to call it legal fraud. I’m not using the term in the technical sense in that sentence, and again, I’m not claiming that it should be illegal.
“I don’t frankly care. If people parties to an agreement don’t take the time to specify it carefully enough, they are to blame. If enough people are harmed by the wrong legal presumption, then practices will change. ”
I agree. I just find it funny that some libertarians (not you, but IIRC it was PE in this thread) claim the need to create legal privileges to make it easier for a given class to accomplish its objectives. I merely suggest that if you want contractually limited liability, it is fairly easy to include a standard clause in every contract you make. Then there can be no argument that the parties weren’t aware of some convenient legal fiction. It would revert back to standard contract analysis. However, I will agree to the extent that this is, in general, not a very big deal. But it is important to note that it isn’t fundamentally sound.
“Sure. But I find that a-libertarian. Interesting, but irrelevant.”
Fine – but you were the one to post his article. And further, as noted above, I’m clarifying my position contra the “you people” that you seem to confuse me with.
September 28, 2006 at 1:09 pm
-
As an aside, if we argue liability in situations involving corporations, we shouldn’t forget that corporations are persons at law. As legal creatures it must act through physical beings, ie, corporate managers and employees. As such, imputing liability from managers and employees to corporation is very easy and commonly accepted today.
Further, pass-through liability to a corporation by necessity implies direct liability of employee and manager. So if I am hurt by employee of corporation, I get my compensation from employee and corporation, jointly and severally.
Directors can also be liable. (If employees and managers are arms and legs, then directors are brains — as hard as it may be to swallow while witnessing the Hewlett Packard fiasco involving the ladies who ran board, ran in-house counsel and used to run corporation…). Directors usually have something in their contract that says corporation will pay all bills unless director intentionally and knowingly acted in an illegal manner, etc.
Shareholders can only be liable to extent of their capital contribution to enterprise or money paid for shares.
That said, in libertania, if corporations existed (which I maintain would not be the case any more than cow pie pizza would exist in libertania), attributing liability to shareholders would be be difficult even without grant of immunity by ___________. This is because shareholders are not technically on site for the wrongdoing. But beware, if you are a shareholder of a corporation and, while in the course and scope of your duty as an employee of the corporation, you commit a tort, you are on the hook for the whole kit and kabooble notwithstanding your shareholder status.
But if you only own shares and are kicking back in Houston eating cow pies when the tort is committed by the corporate employee in Oklahoma, of course there is no liability to you. (Some may argue that giving the employee instructions to commit the tort somehow imposes liability on our cow pie loving shareholder, but I doubt that for many reasons, beginning with the concept that shareholders don’t give order to corporate employees, managers do, and managers get their instructions from directors, and directors almost NEVER ask for shareholder approval first.)
Oh, and corporations serve no purpose in real life. At all.
September 28, 2006 at 1:53 pm
-
Oh, and corporations serve no purpose in real life. At all.
Dude, I have trouble believing you are serious here. This is just bizarre.
As an aside, if we argue liability in situations involving corporations, we shouldn’t forget that corporations are persons at law.
I assume you have actually read Hessen and are familiar w/ his extended discussion of this issue?
As legal creatures it must act through physical beings, ie, corporate managers and employees. As such, imputing liability from managers and employees to corporation is very easy and commonly accepted today.
This does not imply that it’s justified to automatically hold a shareholder vicariously liable for the actions performed by other people (which actions? which people?).
Further, pass-through liability to a corporation by necessity implies direct liability of employee and manager.
liability for what, exactly? For what actios? For those of some monk in timbuktu?
Directors can also be liable.
Sure, why not–if and to the extent it is establihsed they are vicariously responsible for the tort in question?
That said, in libertania, if corporations existed (which I maintain would not be the case any more than cow pie pizza would exist in libertania), attributing liability to shareholders would be be difficult even without grant of immunity by ___________. This is because shareholders are not technically on site for the wrongdoing. But beware, if you are a shareholder of a corporation and, while in the course and scope of your duty as an employee of the corporation, you commit a tort, you are on the hook for the whole kit and kabooble notwithstanding your shareholder status.
Lee, what in the world are you talking about?
But if you only own shares and are kicking back in Houston eating cow pies when the tort is committed by the corporate employee in Oklahoma, of course there is no liability to you.
Uhhh…. so you are disagreeing w/ us how?
All we are maintaining is this. First, by contrat people can become limited liability “shareholders” liable only to the extent of their initial investment, to third parties who contract with the company. Second, *merely holding shares* does not appear to involve the shareholder in enough active control of what employees of the company do to make them vicariously liable for whatever the company is vicariously liable for in tort. That is all. I think you people are all very confused about what it is you are arguing against.
September 28, 2006 at 2:24 pm
-
Stephan,
Okay, I am having some fun here, but I don’t mean to be obtuse.
—
You say:“All we are maintaining is this. First, by contract people can become limited liability “shareholders” liable only to the extent of their initial investment, to third parties who contract with the company. Second, *merely holding shares* does not appear to involve the shareholder in enough active control of what employees of the company do to make them vicariously liable for whatever the company is vicariously liable for in tort. That is all. I think you people are all very confused about what it is you are arguing against.”
—
Assuming contract law in libertania allows for this, I agree with this statement. I only ask whether corporations as we now undertand them to be would exist in libertania. And the answer has to be nay. There may be some creature similar to corporation, but not corporation.As for my example of shareholder who is also employee, surely you agree that if I create “Cow Pie, Inc.” and then hop in the cowpie-mobile and run Person over on the highway, my shareholder status would not reduce my liability to Person in the slightest. I just mentioned this point in passing because some people think the corporate shield shields actual acts by individuals. Not so. Person would be entitled to judgement against me and my corporation.
September 28, 2006 at 2:27 pm
-
Lee: “Assuming contract law in libertania allows for this, I agree with this statement. I only ask whether corporations as we now undertand them to be would exist in libertania. And the answer has to be nay. There may be some creature similar to corporation, but not corporation.”
But this is ridiculous. marriage as we now konw it would not exist in libertania, since it would not be a creature of the state. Does that mean there would be no marriage in a free society?
“As for my example of shareholder who is also employee, surely you agree that if I create “Cow Pie, Inc.” and then hop in the cowpie-mobile and run Person over on the highway, my shareholder status would not reduce my liability to Person in the slightest.”
Uh— of course not. It does not NOW.
September 28, 2006 at 3:16 pm
-
Ridiculous? You jest.
Alternative forms of marriage will exist. It will likely be Christian in nature, but maybe it will be Muslim or something else. In modern civil law marriage has a different meaning and effect than in, say, classical Christian communities. Today, I can get a marriage certificate from the state that has a fixed set of rights/obligations (if you are male, it’s mostly obligations, but I digress…as eddie murphy joked “eddie, I want half!”). In libertania things will be different. So, too, with business entities.
What’s so ridiculous about that?
September 28, 2006 at 4:05 pm
-
Score so far:
QB: 10
NSK: 1It would be closer but QB scores multiples for making the same logical point over and over but NSK simply can’t comprehend. NSK scores one big point (the first point) for saying that “corporations” could exist without a state and no libertarian rule could prevent it.
September 28, 2006 at 6:51 pm
-
Mr. Kinsella and Quasibill,
I’ve been quite pleased to see something approaching a consensus emerging on these issues, but have one technical point to make about terminology, which I think is important:
The drunken truck driver employee who runs over the child is “directly liable.”The employer who knowingly sends the drunk employee out after smelling the stench of moonshine on him may be held liable on one of two theories:
-He is “indirectly liable” if he was negligent or somehow causally responsible in the sense that Mr. Kinsella (rightly) insists upon.
-He is “vicariously liable” if he is held liable automatically simply by virtue of the fact that he bears a certain relation to the employee. To the extent that we’re defending the possible responsible of those who did not physically cause the harm, we ought not to call that liability “vicarious” unless, perhaps it can be justifiably said, that a certain class of person’s always would in fact be causally responsible in situations where they did in deed bear a certain sort of relationship to the direct tortfeasor.
That’s all for now,
Araglin
October 13, 2006 at 3:10 pm
-
It is true that modern limited liability statutes only go back to the 19th century – but the concept itself is ancient (the idea of the corporation can be found, for example, in the idea of a church or a university college)
Regardless of the age of the concept (I accept that many evil things are old) there is the point of freedom of contract.
If a group of people (or even one person) say IN ADVANCE “if this business venture goes wrong, we will not sell all we own to pay your loss, we will only give you want we have put into the business” then a customer or supplyer has a choice.
They can refuse to do business with the business these people have set up (i.e. only do business with non limited liabilty concerns where the people who own the business are open to losing all their private wealth – their homes and so on), or they can accept this condition.
It is wrong to do business with something that clearly called itself “Limited” (in Britain) or “Incorporated” (in the United States) and then say “the business has gone bankrupt, but the shareholders still have homes and cars (etc) I demand they pay me!”
Only someone who did not know in advance that they were dealing with a limited liability organization (due to some deception) has a possible case against the shareholders.
Although I am disturbed by the quiet dropping of the term “Limited” (in Britian) and “Incorporated” (in the United States).
A corportaion should not just call itself “I.B.M.” (or whatever) it should be careful to call itself …… INCORPORATED (in the United States) or …….. Limited (in Britain).
After all some organizations are not limited liability (such as Lloyds insurance in Britian) and (on moral if not legal grounds) the practice of just giving their name (without having to state that they are limited liability) should be reserved for them.
No one should have to do business with a limited liability concern without knowing what it is – and be open about what it is should be the responsibility of the limited liability concern.
I am not asking that there should be a great sign outside every building of such an organization saying “If this place goes bust you do not get paid for you have sold us, and you get to watch the shareholders drive off in big cars to their nice houses”, but surely asking for the words “Limited” or “Incorporated” after the name is not asking for too much.
October 14, 2006 at 3:42 am
-
Texas is one of the few regions which have greatly benefited from the tort reforms. Armed with billions of dollars from settlements in the tobacco lawsuits and other big money cases, trial lawyers are seeking to discredit and take away many of the benefits of tort reforms adopted around the country in recent years. Fortunately, a new Texas study is providing facts to combat their campaign of disinformation.
The study looked at inflation, personal income, job creation and other economic factors to determine the success of Tort Reforms, championed by George w. Bush and administration. The overall impact of tort reforms on the Texas economy is estimated to include $ 23.207 billion annual total expenditure for the year 2000. The benefits represent 5.64% of the total income growth, 5.32% of output expansion and 11.4% of the net job creation during 1995-2000. In addition to these specific effects, legal reforms also helped in creating a better environment for economic development within Texas.Tort Reforms were responsible for creating almost 295,151 permanent jobs in Texas during the past few years. This shows that the tax reforms have had a direct and positive impact on the lives of the consumers. The savings to the typical Texas household in terms of lower prices and increased total personal income amount to $1078 annually, and those savings are projected to grow over time. Many of the cases lying unsolved in the courts have now been cleared, giving the citizens greater access to the courts. So the study confirms that tort reforms have benefited the consumers and businesses and also the courts with civil justice reforms.
Mr. http://www.pacificresearch.org/press/clip/2006/clip-05-24-06tlr.html
October 14, 2006 at 1:16 pm
-
Quasibill makes precisely the argument I would make against corporations, and I would go further: the corporation – as it currently exists – is a mechanism by which this “minor” delegatory power is dehumanized by disinvesting responsibility from human actors. It allows the profit motive to attain a rational, dispassionate role disconnected from authentic, personal human agency – in much the same way that the State systematizes the exercise of power to hide what is otherwise naked coercion. Both corporations and the State reflect similar bureaucracies, and this is the product of more than coincidence – although I suppose that is also an “a-libertarian” viewpoint (much as senseless disparagement of “the Left” is, true?).
I also concur with Quasibill that if a business practice such as limited liability is so useful, it doesn’t make sense why it should be institutionalized by State fiat. I happen to think that the State rationalization of business by legal means in favor of certain parties IS a big deal. Simply dismissing unwitting consumers as unsophisticated is insufficiently libertarian. It ignores a massive and complicated corporate legal code that nobody fully understands – another way in which a “system” is substituted for authentic human conscience and masks otherwise unsavory activities.
October 27, 2008 at 1:48 pm
-
Liability:
How does a form of enforcable liability arise other than via a “legal system” having coercive powers, usually derived through the political (and occasionally social) structure.
Thus to say how far and when that power shall be used is really a limit on powers.
On Torts: ever hear of absolute liability without fault?
R. Richard Schweitzer
August 22, 2009 at 12:51 am
-
I’m amazed that the concept of strict liability was completely ignored in this conversation until one person mentioned it two years later.
The overriding concern with tort is to see that the damaged parties are made whole again, as they never entered into a contract or otherwise took any willful risk.
This is why it is important to attach ultimate liability to the property owner, who happens to be responsible for the initial delegation of power.
For obvious reasons, liability should be applied first to the individuals (if any) found to be negligent or worse (although the corporation may be contractually obligated to cover its agents’ liability in certain predetermined circumstances), followed by, if necessary, the assets of the corporation itself. However, it remains imperative to recompense the injured party to the full extent of his damages, should the negligent individuals and the assets of the corporation be insufficient to recompense the damage done.
As was given in example in the related discussion on Kevin Carson’s blog, a corporation operating heavy, potentially dangerous machinery, inherently incurs elevated risk as a cost of doing business, outside the realm of actual negligence (or worse). Nearly everything in society entails a certain amount of risk, and that is generally OK, until someone is hurt. Such injury may be impossible to attribute to a specific act or acts of negligence, even though there remains an injured party in need of recompense and as well a party responsible for the property which incurred the liability. In this case it remains only proper that the injured party be “made whole” once again, at the expense of the owner of the property which bears the casual relationship to the tort.
Why the owner, in cases where their delegatory authority isn’t quite relevant, as there isn’t a specific act of negligence (or worse) to specify blame? Simple, it remains their property which caused the harm. They maintain the existence (and thus actions, if any) of their property, at their sole (presumable) benefit. Thus, they should bear ultimate liability if their property happens to damage someone in an unpredictable fashion outside the scope of negligence or aggression.
This, of course, assumes that you recognize the practical reality that a tortfeasor may be neither an aggressor nor substantively negligent, and yet still incur liability from the small but still real, societally accepted risk that so many actions (especially profitable ones) entail. We take these risks and are not (nor considered) negligent for doing so, yet we ought still to be responsible if we hurt others when those small risks pan out to be real.
I suppose the obvious example is the hypothetical case of a dog on a leash, with no demonstrated or suspected temperament or aggression issues, who, without provocation or forewarning, “snaps” and lashes out at a child passing by on the sidewalk, biting him in the process. Nobody would say such a dog owner is negligent merely for walking his apparently well-tempered dog. Yet, he should still be liable for the damages incurred by the attack. The child, who did not maintain a potentially dangerous chattel, accepted no willful risk, and has no resources to pay for his injuries, should certainly not have to bear damages sustained from an impossibly unpredictable attack while walking peacefully down the sidewalk.
Extrapolating from the example of “heavy machinery”, we see that the resources of a corporation may allow much greater potential harm at what remains an acceptable (read: non-demonstrative of negligence) miniscule risk than what may be redeemable by the assets of the corporation. This is when shareholders should bear ultimate distributive liability for the remainder of the damages, regardless of specific fault, and beyond the value of their initial investment, if necessary. This would simply be one of the risks of owning shares in a company. In reality, the risk would not be immense — proportionally no worse than the risk to random individuals incurred from the cumulative danger of all these societally acceptable miniscule risks which do not imply negligence — only the damages would fall on parties with some relationship to the property at fault.
September 28, 2009 at 7:30 pm
-
All that matters in my mind is this:
It is not possible (under natural law) for multiple individuals to get together and write a contract that absolves ALL parties from liability. Liability may be divided equally, among several parties, or placed on one individual, but it /cannot/ be contracted away entirely. They cannot form a ‘collective person’ and place liability on it.
It doesn’t matter to me how many people are liable, as long as /someone/ is liable. That person will then have the incentive to make sure his business operates morally and responsibly (both socially and financially). If he does not, he will lose everything.
Naturally, contracts will be written so as to give those with greater liability greater ownership, as no one who is liable will want to forfeit his control (and his fate) to an individual who is not held liable.
However, what if Morgan regularly robbed liquor stores with Bob’s gun and Bob received a cut each time a store was robbed?
I think it is rather hard to make the case that Bob should not share the responsibility with Morgan for the losses of the robbed liquor stores.
I do believe that it is hard to make the case that most corporations benefit from the state. On the other hand, it isn’t hard to make the case that executive management of large corporations benefit from the state. There may even come a time when investors will get fed up with it.
Yes, he probably should, because he helped cause it–in the sense that Pat Tinsley and I lay out in the Causation article linked above.
Where is the case? I don’t think this case can be made. Some do. Not all, or even most, IMO.
If Bob knew about the purpose, then anybody would agree. If not, it’s a different story, and every state around the world disagrees in principle, because they immunize every officer that is responsible for the abuse. The state simply claims capricious power to apply the principle at whim.
If Bob knew about the purpose, then anybody would agree. If not, it’s a different story, and every state around the world disagrees in principle, because they immunize every officer that is responsible for any such abuse. The state simply claims capricious power to apply the principle at whim.
I didn’t think I was unclear:
Your “Labor Theory of Value” paragraph simply has no place in this piece. Apart from falsely characterizing the LTV as universally characteristic of left-libertarians (which is apparently its intent), it serves no function whatsoever. It neither introduces nor illuminates any of the subsequent material.
Well, that’s kind of the point.
You didn’t throw in a paragraph falsely claiming all left-libertarians prefer pistachio ice cream.
Or a paragraph falsely claiming all left-libertarians practice bestiality.
Why throw in the false LTV claim, since it has nothing to do with the piece?
You just changed the claim to “some” left-libertarians. The original claim was universal in scope. I can prove the original claim wrong with two four-word sentences:
I am a left libertarian. I am an Austrian subjectivist.
QED, not all left libertarians are LTV supporters.
All that said, my objection is less that the claim is false than that it has nothing whatsoever to do with anything in the rest of the piece. It’s as relevant to the question you’re addressing as the pistachio or bestality claims would be, which is to say not relevant at all.
I don’t remember making it universal. But if it was, I would agree that it is wrong insofar as some self-described “left-libertarians” reject this hoary doctrine. Okayyy. But then, you would need to carefully and rigorously define what ‘left-libertarian” means.
Okay. I am glad.
So, may I assume you join me in rejecting the LTV views of the other left-libs?
Right–so it’s like an editor’s comment. THanks, and as I said, it was jsut a blog post.
blockquote> It’s as relevant to the question you’re addressing as the pistachio or bestality claims would be, which is to say not relevant at all.
IT seems to me that what is relevant is substantive truth and accuracy, not the “appropriateness” of the placement of a given commentary.
I reject all variants of the Labor Theory of Value of which I am aware, regardless of whom is advocating for said theory.
“Value” is entirely subjective. What is something worth? Whatever it’s worth to the person valuing it.
Even the instrument of “price” doesn’t reflect some imaginary “objective” value. All that can be said about the price of an unsold item is that it reflects at least the lowest value its would-be seller places on it, and that nobody’s come along yet who places a higher value than that on it. All that can be said about price of a sold item is that it sold for at or more than the lowest value the seller placed on it, and for at or less than the highest value the buyer placed on it.
I am glad you say this, but elsewhere you said:
This implies, I am afraid, that you “own” your “labor” and its “results”.
This is all metaphorical, non-rigorous, liberal arts confusion.
Kinsella: “We have to recognize that the prima facie answer—the default condition—is no: each person is responsible only for his own torts, not for those of others. To hold someone else liable requires some kind of “vicarious liability” theory. ”
The pit bull can’t pay, so his owner is responsible. Same with the owners of corporations. No need for any “vicarious liability” theory because there is nothing vicarious about the relationship nor the liability of an owner for his pit bull or her corporation. There is no “vicarious liability” theory involved because there is no “someone else.” There is only the owner.
Kinsella: “But holding employers—or shareholders—vicariously liable for actions of their employees relies on the offensive, paternalistic, feudalistic concept of respondeat superior—a master is responsible for his slaves’ or servants’ transgressions. As Hessen notes, this is just a vestige of the medieval mentality. Why would a shareholder be liable for actions of some employee?”
What is offensive is this is that this statement is deceptive and utter nonsense. The agent-principal relationship is alive and well in law and in relationships recognized as such throughout the world. It is ancient, of course, but most truths are, and modern lawyers are as unable to refute them as were their medieval predecessors down through the ages. Why didn’t the author or Hessen use this modern, non-offensive, non-paternalistic, non-feudalistic term? And since you repeat the same unjustified assertions over and over, let me also be repetitive: We are not talking about a “stockholder” liability for “some employee,” what the author is talking about is an owner’s responsibility for his or her potentially dangerous property or operation. The author would incise the owner from his property, but the ownership of property (viz., private property) is crucial to every libertarian theory I have ever encountered.
Kinsella: “On the other hand…he may have bought the share from a previous shareholder. ”
This is a silly argument. Whether one bought the pit bull as a puppy or a trained fighting dog is immaterial to our owner’s relationship to the property.
Kinsella: ” They assume that giving money to the corporation is akin to “aiding and abetting it…”
This is a strawman, one of so many in this article that I can’t even begin to count them let alone address them all. For this one let me just say, no one need assume anything of the sort, and I doubt anyone so assumes. No owner (stockholder) of a business “gives” it money. An owner either creates the business by an initial investing, or buys it as a going concern. Obviously how ownership is obtained has no affect whatsoever on the pit bull’s behavior nor on whether or not the reactor core melts during a tsunami. Nor does this point have any place in a *rational* argument. Like the argument in total, it is a lawyer-like attempt to ameliorate if not eliminate the personal responsibility involved in human action upon which liberty utterly depends.
If I were to characterize the argument in this article, as it characterizes any imagined opposing view, the kindest thing I could say is that it is silly. Not only is personal responsibility compatible with libertarian theory, it is the ultimate foundation of liberty. The author’s attempt to relieve owners of responsibility for their pit bulls or their dangerous operations engaged in for profit is essentially an attack on individual liberty in the manner of a lawyer defending a losing cause with one frivolous argument piled upon another until the judge finally orders her to “shut up.”
I could pick the rest of the article apart straw man by indirect ad hominem aimed at whoever might have the temerity to oppose this sanctimonious view, but suffice to say again that the only “vicarious” relationship is a figment of a creative imagination. And if my counter to this diatribe should be characterized as left-libertarian, I would have to classify this article as pure statist, but that would be adopting the methodology of this author’s endeavor to oppose personal responsibility and the individual liberty resulting therefrom.
There are other good reasons why corporations, which are purely products of State legislation, are harmful to liberty not addressed by the article. One big one is the so-called “legal fiction,” which holds that corporations are “persons” for the purpose of standing in legal proceedings. As a direct result of this fiction, many court rulings (including those of the Supreme Court) have been made in cases wherein the parties were the State and a corporation which established important precedents, which precedents were later applied to cases involving the State and individuals as though the latter were equivalent to corporations and without the human rights that can only be claimed by individuals. An example of this is the famous case of Brushaber vs. Union Pacific Railroad (http://laws.lp.findlaw.com/getcase/us/240/1.html), in which SCOTUS declared that the newly enacted federal income tax did not violate the Constitution as claimed in that case and therefor Union Pacific must pay it. From then (1916) until the present, that case has been cited in lower federal courts as having determined that the income tax was constitutional. It has been cited as precedent to deflect thousands of cases of individuals who have tried to challenge the constitutionality of the income tax as applied by the IRS against them, even though Brushaber never even considered the constitutionality of the income tax as applied to real individuals who are not legal fictions created by State legislation.
The State and corporations are so intimately tied to one another that defending the latter is virtually defending the State and its illicit powers, without which no corporation has ever existed.
Mr. Kinsella, I’ve embraced your arguments in opposition to intellectual property. IMHO, in this case you’re case falls flat.
There’s a marked difference between owning a dangerous piece of property and owning shares in a corporation — in the former case, a person has complete control over the thing in question because this is what ownership mean. In the latter, a person is a party to various and sundry contracts and has only as much control and say as those contracts allow.
As for your claims that respondeat superior liability is widely recognized, I will point out that being in widespread use today does not make it right. Plenty of other legal systems get by fine without the concept. Some of those systems would even say that a person is not liable for paying someone else to commit an intentional tort against another person!
In short, you shouldn’t be so dismissive of NSK’s arguments. He’s well read on this subject and knows what he’s talking about. Look into his sources and go beyond the overview presented here. I think you’ll come around to NSK’s view here just like you came around on IP.
Well you are just buying into the state’s classifications. Who says he “is” an “owner”? Ownership is the right to control. What resource does he have the right to control?
well if you call him an owner, as the state says, I guess you are done! How convenient for you. And why, again, does the right to control a resource imply that you are responsible for harms caused with that resource being used as a causal means? I realize you just want to rely on this without justifying it –but bear with me–how do you know this?
Is your chauffer or delivery man your property? do you own him?
Again, you are speaking simplistically. Did you read my post? I explained the problems with assuming ownership implies liability. And in any case, the owner of a corporation owns property, not people. Helloooo
So…. if a fedex truck driver runs you over, he is not really there?
Well that settles it, then! Let’s hang up libertarian theorizing–the “world” has “established” the “right way” to proceed!
Ah, well when you put it that way it’s all settled! Wow.
So… owning a piece of paper that represents a legal title to a sliver of a legal claim to the assets of a firm upon dissolution is … “dangerous”, “like” a pit bull? Wow.
It’s not a strawman at all. Since you ignorami cannot even articulate a coherent explanation of how corporations work much less what is your theory of rights or liability or causation, I am tyring to help you out by charitably articulating your implicit views for you.
This sounds like an amateur observation by a clueless grad student in a dorm room session bullshitting about stuff they have no clue about. With David Letterman playing in the background, and the whiff of Mary Jane from the suite-mate next door. Good for you! But when you buy a share of Exxon stock from a previous owner, using the stock market to facilitate the exchange, how do you “buy it”?–and what is “it?”; as a “going concern”–and pray tell, what is the relevance of GAAP terminology like “going concern” to libertarian theory? methinks you are utterly clueless.
With a “private” individual, generally, s/he is the owner, and s/he is responsible for their or their business’s actions. Responsible in law, but also, responsible as a member of a social group.
The corporation is a legal fiction, stemming from one off investments in colonial times, where the shareholder could lose only what s/he invested. The ensuing imperialism, based primarily on the profit motive, led to some horrendous outcomes, many of which the world is still, indirectly, dealing with (I am not claiming that ‘only’ corporations were responsible but they played a significant role).
We look for someone to blame, to take responsibility for actions that cause harm to others. When a corporation is the face of that blame, it rarely suffers as a private individual would. Even something as seemingly insignificant as social stigma can have a heavy effect on an individual and the way the rest of society relates to them – conversely, a corporation can perform a whitewash, pay off some directors and replace them. It is harder for an individual to do this, “finding God” may work once with one or two people but, generally ‘man’ is viewed by their actions. The corporation can blame previous corporate culture (ie the actual “real” people) and continue on with little real consequences after time.
If Dr Evil is responsible for forcing native Australians into slavery to ensure profits in his pearl diving industry, Dr Evil may well have his life shortened by someone who cares (I am being extreme only to stress a point). The Dutch East India company will simply replace their pearl diving manager with another individual who will likely carry on the same business practices.
Netterville was more thorough in his analysis of your paper, and I find his points compelling. I have tried to limit my position, to this single point of “responsibility and consequences”.
It is likely that, rather than “shares”, a firm seeking investment could sell bonds. In effect, claims upon future profits without any claim of ownership.
I’m quite curious why the shift occurred, to the assumption now that stockholders always exercise ownership privileges, rather than a “share” of the “stock”.
A share of stock in a corporation is an undivided ownership interest in the assets of that corporation.
Because it’s an undivided interest among many, control is exercised through collective instrumentalities, and there are options for exercising more control (common stock) or less control (preferred stock) as compared to other owners of interest, but the claim that control is not exercised is absurd.
“Is your chauffer or delivery man your property? do you own him?”
I own his work — that’s what employment is.
That’s how the state’s positive law classifies it. So what? Is it libertarian? Is it accurate? Do I, as a Google share owner, have a right to use the HQ for a meeting or the google corporate jet for transportation?
In any case: you guys seem wedded to the conventional notion that if you own something you “are” “responsible” for “it”. Why? This is not libertarian. Ownerhip is the right to control. It does not mean you are responsible for anything involving those means, unless you employ them as means.
Well I don’t think Rothbard, Pilon, and Hessen’s careful arguments about this are absurd.
Nonsense. You are in thrall to imprecise and metaphorical–maybe leftish?–concepts. No one owns “work”. Not the worker, not the employer. Work is just an action. You don’t own your actions. This is nonsense. It leads to confusion and imprecision. You own your body. Period. Not your “work”.
Like you say, ownership is the right to control.
You have the right to control — in other words you own — your actions.
The employer-worker relationship is an agreed transfer, on given terms, of ownership of the right to control certain of one’s actions, e.g. “from 9am to 5pm, Monday thru Friday, my hands will be doing what YOU want them to be doing rather than what I’d otherwise have them doing, in return for which you shall pay me $X.”
I disagree completely. First, the employment relationship is NOT one of slavery. The employer does NOT own the employee. HE does NOT own the employee’s body, or time, or actions. Rather, he transfers title to money on the condition that the employee use his body to perform certain specified actions. The employee’s ability to control his body, combined with his legally recognized right to his body, gives him the legal and practical ability to decide to perform an action to trigger the payment, or to withold services to induce the employer to enter into the bargain. IN short: the employment agreement is a one-way transfer of title: of money, which is conditionally transferred upon a certain specified triggering condition (which happens to be an action the employee can perform). But the action is not owned by either the employee or employer.
Right?
I find your elaborate construction more confusing than my simpler one.
Energy and the direction of it (“action”) are scarce resources, and I own some of them by virtue of having created them from other scarce resources (e.g. food) which I homesteaded or otherwise honestly acquired.
Since I own them, I can sell them. And in a wage labor scenario, that’s exactly what I’m doing.
As an example, when I worked at a factory where boat trailers were built, I was not selling the factory owner X trailers per day. Sometimes I came to work and was put to work loading trailers onto trucks for shipment. Sometimes I came to work and was put to work on the assembly line, hanging trailer parts on racks to be run through a paint sprayer and oven. One time, for about two weeks, I came to work and was told to get in a minivan and pull this or that trailer to this or that boat factory so that the fit between prototype boat and prototype trailer could be tested. The result of my work and the work of others was X trailers, but that’s not what the employer was buying from me. He was buying the use of my body and my energy at his direction for a set period of time.
As a side note, I don’t consider commodification of labor or the wage system to be inherently exploitative in some evil way as some left libertarians seem to. I suspect that the incidence of wage labor would go down, and its price up, in a freed market, but my toes would still be tapping if that were not the case.
Okayyy… but… so? this is an irrelevant comment, and distracts from substance.
No you don’t. This is all confusion and liberal arts metaphorical nonsense. You don’t own energy, or the “direction of it”. Now you wonder why I accused you guys of falling prey to a version of the labor theory of value.
Wrong. This does not follow at all. A huge confusion. Owning something does not mean you can sell it: for example your body (or do you believe in voluntary slavery?!).
And selling something does not mean you own it: You do not own your actions but you do own your body which gives you the ability to perform, or withhold, certain actiosn and thus “exchange” or “sell” them for payment.
“And in a wage labor scenario, that’s exactly what I’m doing.”
No, it is not “exactly” what you are doing at all. In a wage labor “scenario,” you are simply using your rights over your body to induce an employer to agree to transfer title to money to you if you perform certain actions. That is all. It is a one-way transfer of title. There is no *legal* exchange.
Right: legally speaking you were not “selling” anything, since you did not part with title to anything that you owned. How hard is this to grok?
Economically, he gave you title to his money, in “exchange” for getting “what he wanteD” which was your “doing X”. But that does not mean you owned X, or that you transferred title to X or to “doing X” to him. This is just a confusion. You guys really need to read Rothbard’s title transfer theory of contract. Sheesh.
I don’t either, but I really don’t care if it is, since “exploitation” is not aggression, and thus exploitation, whatever this means, is not a rights violation.
Clearly, there are different flavors of “ownership,” but the idea that the work product of personal energy expenditure is somehow divorced from the person expending it, I find totally nonsensical.
I’m certainly willing to consider any clarifying theory, though. Especially as it might help sort out a simple, ethically actionable common denominator for various kinds of ownership.
How else would one interpret relationships within an institution created by state fiat than with reference to “the state’s positive law?” Get rid of the state’s positive law and the corporation doesn’t exist, so the question goes away.
The right-libertarian argument that criticism of corporations are illegitimate since institutions like corporations might come into existence absent the state is like arguing that since some other economic actor in some other economic system might produce a car like the Volvo 740 wagon, it’s illegitimate to complain about the seat-warmer in my actual 740 wagon not working.
How is it that you think you know that?
“Same with corporations. At present they are companies, or firms, that receive a certain entity status from the state. Remove state incorporation and they remain companies with shareholders, employees, assets, products, contracts, customers. The company would exist. Amazon Inc. would now be Amazon LLP or Amazon Firm or whatever.”
Agreed. Companies absent state privilege would still be companies — companies without state privilege.
“So what?”
Yup.
You don’t.
Cool. Thanks for resolving that. Now that I know that, I’m just going to scrawl “you didn’t own those 667 kilowatt hours that I used last month, or the direction of them to my breaker box, so I’m not paying you for them” on my bill from Ameren UE instead of paying it.
“Owning something does not mean you can sell it: for example your body (or do you believe in voluntary slavery?!).”
No, I don’t believe in voluntary slavery any more than I believe in dry water. If it’s voluntary, it isn’t slavery. And if I can’t sell something, I don’t own it.
This is eristic. This sarcasm proves nothing. Today’s contract law is based on the idea of binding promises backed by consideration, for one. So who cares about what current law is? Are we legal positivists? Second, the contract can be viewed as a single unilateral title transfer from customer to “Ameren” [I assume this is some yankee utility company]: I hereby transfer $x to you IF such-and-such event happens (where the event may be: provision of certain kilowatts of electricity; it could aslo be: “if it rains tomorrow,” which does not mean either party “owns” the rain).
Evasion. The question in libertarian circles is whether a contract to sell your body into slavery is legally enforceable. Your trite formulation in your last sentence sounds like that of a politician, and does not answer the issue.
This is nonsense. Ownership means right to control. It is not obvious that the right to control implies the “rihgt to sell”. This is yet another assumption unbacked by anything but inchoate intuition and not carefully squared with other libertarian property rights principles.
Whether or not something is “legally enforceable” is, as you’ve pointed out numerous times, irrelevant to whether or not it is a right.
If I (voluntarily) contract to sell my body, it’s not slavery, any more than if I (voluntarily) contract to sell something else I own it’s robbery.
Slavery is involuntary servitude.
“It is not obvious that the right to control implies the ‘right to sell.’ ”
The right to control does not imply the right to sell, it subsume it. The specific activity of “selling” is an instance of the broader category of activities of “controlling.”
Correct. I should have said, whether it ought to be legally enforceable.
the contract is not slavery, but enforcing it might be. You are aware of the debate in this area, right? And you realize most libertarians do not believe a contract to sell your body ought not be enforceable, right? And I would think almost no left-libertarians think voluntary slavery agreements ought to be legally enforceable.
To enforce a slavery contract the master would need to be able to legitimately use force against the slave’s body, if the slave tried to run away, if he tried to change his mind. At that point, it would be involuntary–that is, not consented to. Your argumet would then be, “no no, he consented earlier, and that consent…. is somehow irrevocable.” Your argument relies on this last key step: saying that an earlier grant of permission cannot be undone; that you cannot change your mind. BUt where does libertarianism say this? Suppose a girl consents to a kiss. THe guy kisses her. It’s not a battery, since it’s consented to. What if she says, “You may kiss me anytime you like, from now to the end of time!” and so the guy plants a kiss on her at random times, every day, over the following week. Then one day she gets upset with him, and says, “Don’t you ever kiss me!” If he kisses her now, it is not with her consent. Why not? Because she changed her mind. Because when an action is to be performed that uses the body or property of, or that changes the physical integrity of, or that crosses the borders of, someone else, the question is of course: at the time of the use, is it consented to or not? And so that is just a question of proof and evidence and communication: if the person just said 3 seconds ago “go ahead” then we reasonably assume that he is consenting now. That is, the previous communication serves as evidence that this is a standing order or standing presumption he has set up, that persists until the moment of use. In the kissing example the girl’s consent given a week earlier persists into the future, as a default presumption of what her consent is at the time of each kissing act. Yet that is only because she has not changed this default assumption with a new communication.
If I step into the boxing ring to box you, we both consent to blows. If I say I will box you tomorrow, but then 5 seconds before stepping into the ring I get cold feet, you can’t physically drag me into the ring so that you can hit me.
Same with a guy who promises to be a slave. So long as he does not object to following orders or letting the master hit him, no problem; but when he changes his mind, at that point, he is no longer consenting.
I don’t think you’ve thought this through. You’re assuming that an contingent incident of one type of ownership is an essential feature of ownership per se. Ownership means the legal right to control. That does not imply the right to get rid of the right to control. I have explained this in detail elsewhere, e.g. http://blog.mises.org/18608/the-relation-between-the-non-aggression-principle-and-property-rights-a-response-to-division-by-zer0/ and http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/17_2/17_2_2.pdf . When you, as a body-owning agent, use your rightful control over your body to engage in the action of appropriating some previously-unowned and unused external scarce resource, then you become its owner by homesteading. This type of ownership can obviously be undone by the nature of its origin: an acquired thing can be un-acquired, or abandoned. The right to abandon it gives rise to the ability to sell it, since you can abandon it “to” a given recipient. Thus, the nature of ownership of acquired things means that you can, in fact, sell or give away the thing. However, the same is not true of the nature of ownership of our bodies, since we do not acquire our bodies by homesteading, in the same way; there is no original act of body-appropriation to “undo”. You own your body because of your intimate connection with it, not because you homesteaded it.
Thus, ownership does not imply the right to sell.
Only if the contract is defective in some respect.
“You are aware of the debate in this area, right?”
I’m aware of the existence of discussions in this area, and of their content. Characterizing those discussions as “debate” seems to be to me taking it a little far, given the crystal clarity of the matter. If it’s a voluntary contract, it’s not slavery, period.
“And you realize most libertarians do not believe a contract to sell your body ought not be enforceable, right?”
No, I was not aware of that. And I’m still not.
“And I would think almost no left-libertarians think voluntary slavery agreements ought to be legally enforceable.”
Since there’s no such thing as “voluntary slavery agreements” (if it’s a voluntary agreement, it’s not slavery), I suspect you’re right.
“To enforce a slavery contract the master would need to be able to legitimately use force against the slave’s body, if the slave tried to run away, if he tried to change his mind.”
Except that there’s no slave or master involved in the scenario. Your statement is the equivalent of “To enforce a contract under which one party was entitled to a television, that party would need to be able to legitimately use force against anyone trying to take the television, if someone tried to take the television, or if the party who owed and had delivered the television tried to steal it back.”
Which, of course, is in fact that case and is hunky dory in anything resembling rational libertarian theory.
“At that point, it would be involuntary–that is, not consented to.”
Only in the same sense that it would be “involuntary” for you to keep the television that you offered me $100 for, that I accepted $100 for, and that you now possess.
” Your argumet would then be, “no no, he consented earlier, and that consent…. is somehow irrevocable.’”
Whether or not the consent is revocable is a matter of the terms of the contract.
“Your argument relies on this last key step: saying that an earlier grant of permission cannot be undone”
I’m not saying that NO earlier grant of permission can be undone. I’m saying that a binding contract without provisions for its undoing can’t be done at the whim of one party.
You can’t have it both ways. Either you own your body, or you don’t. If you own it, then it is your property, and absent some convincing proof otherwise, the rules that apply to property in general apply to it specifically.
“If I step into the boxing ring to box you, we both consent to blows. If I say I will box you tomorrow, but then 5 seconds before stepping into the ring I get cold feet, you can’t physically drag me into the ring so that you can hit me.”
Actually, whether or not I can do that depends on the terms of any contract we have or don’t have pertaining to the matter.
“Same with a guy who promises to be a slave. So long as he does not object to following orders or letting the master hit him, no problem; but when he changes his mind, at that point, he is no longer consenting.”
And it doesn’t matter whether or not he’s “consenting.” If he’s sold his body, his body no longer belongs to him, so his consent or non-consent is irrelevant.
I think you don’t realize how much you are taking for granted and that you are reversing things, assuming too much. Contract is not a source of rights, as you are implicitly thinking of it; it is just a transfer of title to alienable property. Rothbard wrote on this in Ethics of Liberty. You could profit from reading it. This means that you can only transfer title to things that are alienable. You can’t assume it’s alienable because you make a contract. That’s question-begging. It’s frustrating you can’t see this. You can’t just make these mainstream-ish pronouncements relying on legal doctrines as if it settles it. You are just engaged in question-begging, because you apparently cannot even see that you are doing it.
It’s not crystal clear at all, and you are just being obstinate here. Talk to your fellow libertarians, man. This is an empirical matter, but I’d be willing to put some money on it.
Well, then I think you are a bit clueless. Ask around.
I cannot debate you on this if you are going to pettifog. You konw what i’m talking about. This is eristic and not serious, Tom. We are not really having a semantic debate, are we? If so, I’m not interested.
This is such eristic nonsense. Put effing quotes around “slave” and “master” if you want. Are you just trying to evade serious discussion? If so, you are doing a good job.
You are qeustion begging again. Can you not see this? This is now how you establish your point dude. YOu can’t show that contract includes the power to sell or bind your body, by just asserting that if you make a contract with the right terms it is effective to do this. tHat is just restating your conclusion.
THe questio nis whether it is “binding”. You seem to be totally unfamiliar wiht the libertarian view of contract–again, i urge you to read rothbard’s ethics of liberty chapter on this. Contracts have nothing to do with “binding” promises. They are just transfers of title to alienable property. And you can’t prove that bodies are alienable propety just by saying that you can make a contract to bind yoursefl–this is a perfect case of question-begging, circular reasoning.
I’m not thinking of contract as a source of rights, either explicitly or implicitly. Contract is merely an instrument. You can only contract with things you “own” — a word which we seem to agree means “have a right to control.”
Which brings this whole discussion down to the notion of property as alienable or inalienable. I have never seen any good case for the existence of the latter.
I think you are, when you characterize it as binding obligations.
But then you are question begging since you are assuming “right to control” implies “right to bind/alienate my future decisions about how to control”. It is question-begging, whether you see it or not. I am not saying you are wrong: there are good arguments for body-alienability. But you are not making them. You are question-begging. You apparently do not even see that your proposition is controversial and that you bear the burden of proof. You think it’s sufficient to hand-wave and spout statist legal positivistic legal doctrines as if that settles the issue. Sort of how the Civil War “settled” the issue of secession, I suppose.
Which brings this whole discussion down to the notion of property as alienable or inalienable. I have never seen any good case for the existence of the latter.
I believe that: you don’t seem to have read much in this area. I’ve given you resources: my articles, and many cites therein; Rothbard’s contract theory. You can handwave and pretend it’s simple, but you are wrong. And you are also wrong to think most libertarians would agree that a contract binding your body ought to be legally enforceable–or so I think: I’d bet good money on it. Find 5 of them. There’s you, Walter Block, and … crickets chirping.
I most manifestly do NOT bear the burden of proof. We both agree that I own my body. If you think there’s something I shouldn’t be able to do with that which I own, it’s your job to prove that to me, not my job to prove it to you.
As far as previously made arguments on the subject go, I’ve read some of them. I guess I’ll go re-read some of them, after looking back up the trail that we took into this dry hole to decide whether or not it’s worth it.
Again, you do not seem to see the issue. Yes, we agree you own your body. But that just means we agree that you have the right to decide who gets to use it. That is what we agree on. You are equivocating b/c you are saying we agree on ownership, but we only agree that you have the right to control your body; then you later use the ownership-means-right-to-sell meaning in an equivocating way.
You are so stuck in conventional legal thinking that you cannot see your error. You think “ownership of COURSE means the ‘right to sell’”. But that is wrong.
the “dry hole” is your arguing that we ought to be able to sell ourselves into slavery. sorry, “slavery.” Yeah, um, that’s really what will win over democrats to our side….
If the people protesting the injustice (perceived or real) of Wall Street Billionaires continuing to fatten their pocketbooks at the direct expense of working people is offensive to you because it doesn’t meet your intellectual standards regarding their ‘corporate personhood’ argument, then I suppose there is no real harm in making an argument out of it and declaring yourself a winner. I think that you could just as easily make the argument that it is unlawful and immoral to use the power of government to deprive one class of people of their rights (property – through taxation) to protect another class’ property through this privilege.
Do you not understand the damage that it does to all of us, our rights and our society to perpetuate the myth that what is good for corporations is good for the people? If not, I don’t think a thorough explanation will help.
Balderdash!
Rich
Or do you fail to understand its relevance to your argument?
Perhaps you misunderstood.
Try that same sentiment using quotes with “corporate personhood”: “Corporate Personhood” is what prevents me from buying raw milk from the organic farm two miles away from me in the neighboring state. Is there some general truth to that? If so, then I’ll agree to your rhetoric about negroes and concentration camps.
I find it extremely relevant. It is not incoherent to me. As a matter of fact I think it to be a foundational precept for all further debate.
“All human action arises from self-interest.” That may be a vague bromide to some, but is it not an elementary precept upon which all of Praxeology is constructed?*
*Please don’t digress with this. It was meant rhetorically.
Here, let me translate Richard’s initial claim into a more specific state of higher relevancy:
The purpose of a corporate charter is to contractually bind a private interest with that of public interest?
I found the points of debate in this entire post endlessly fascinating until the lack thereof on Richard’s point. Your lack of debate on Richard’s point seemed to make the rest of it rather pointless.
Person A is asked by person B to take him to a bank, being a good friend, person A obliges. After being dropped off at the bank, person B procedes to rob the bank, and then leaves.
Unaware of anythng amiss, person A drives off with person B.
Police soon catch up and person A immediately pulls over and submits to arrest.
Now this:
Person A knows person B plans to rob a bank and agrees to help him by driving. He drives to the bank and person B procedes, as before, with the robbery. Person A drives off with person B but soon the police catch up. Person A pulls over, realizing there was no use in trying to escape and submits to arrest.
Certainly, you could be tempted to say that the first person is not guilty but the second certainly is, but quickly it becomes apparent that this is in practice absurd. No one can know the workings of another persons mind, and therefore cannot, by the very laws of physics, be allows as evidence in a court room.
In neither instance did person A do anything objectively wrong, and therefore cannot, and should not, be prosecuted for thievery.
Crimes are in actions, not thoughts.
You are further wrong when you say that a person holding a knife threatingly to another person is simply an act of speech and is aggression because of the intentions of the individual in question. This is wrong, holding a knife threateningly puts the victim at *objective* risk, that he would not otherwise be in, regaurdless of the intentions of the knife wielder.
Perhaps I am misunderstanding your position. I hope I am, because you seem to intelligent for this, Kinsella.
Let us take the example of the entrepreneurial plumber with 3 crews. Creditors do not care whether his bookkeeper absconded with the money to feed her coke habit without his knowledge. They will sell his house anyway. I believe it should remain the same for voting shareholders and their executive proxies.
The fundamental issue is not retribution. It is reputation and trust. For without it, markets do not work well. Certainly banks were run much more conservatively when they were partnerships. And no personal fortunes will restore most large bankruptcies. But none of those points represent the motive for changing the law.
Further, the change might generate positive rippling effects. We strongly suspect the very nature of audits and their process and goals would almost immediately change for the better. Likewise, FASB rules on financial statement clarity might find new advocates. Certainly the days of Boards filled with cronies and non-experts would be gone.
If corporations are people, and I argue they are, then markets demand their primary stance is one of mature responsibility, honor and dependability. We ensure that psychological and emotive stance, especially of its leaders and whoever has substantial skin in the game, with their personal treasure.
One might argue that corporations will quickly adapt so that there is no apparent leader, or otherwise incorporate in such a way that ALL employees are proxies for the voting shareholders, so they are all liable. In a sense, they already are. But that aside, who cares? I would be excited to see how such an organization functioned. Our hierarchies too often obscure the fact that that is exactly the kind of responsibility we expect of humans in a free society.
One might respond that personal insurance of executives would rise. So what? In some industries, it would rise higher than others. That is arguably a good outcome to the extent it naturally priced the potential for negative externality into each industry. Essentially the same argument could be made for the cost of borrowing.
One might respond that it will reduce risk and therefore innovation. This argument is hardly worth making; large companies are anything but innovative. They live on annuities. It is small collections of entrepreneurs that innovate, and they are already risking everything.
In summary, we let the owners of capital off the hook regarding a fundamental requirement of free societies. In the same way I am wary of a consultant who tells me what to do with my money, I am wary of making a deal with anyone who does not have considerable investment on the line. It has a way of steadying their words and deeds. This should be the entry price of everyone in a free society. Bar none.
Private property rights need to be applied correctly to finance as well. The usury paid for the use of capital belongs exclusively to the individual owner of that capital. The banker is only due a service fee (which should be made clear within the transactions). A banker who invests depositor’s capital and keeps the usury is a thief. Allow me to reiterate that, and really think about the personal property rights couched in this situation: A banker who invests depositor’s capital and keeps the usury is a thief. And shouldn’t we all ask who is the owner of fiat money? And to whom is the usury due?
The above are two ways that wealth is centralized, i.e. gathered in from the many under a controlling group which goes about using it as if it were their own. This is done by violating the private property rights of individuals. This ethical fact is not ameliorated by the fact that these are voluntary exchanges. Choices always come down to the best of the options presented. Those who present the options control the choice. The defense of the personhood of corporations is not the defense of individual liberties nor of “the free market.” Corporations are not based on individual liberties and do not deserve the championing that the right gives them.