≡ Menu

Where I’ve Changed My Mind

[From my Webnote series]

See other biographical pieces here.

Our views evolve over time. My core libertarian beliefs have not changed much in the last thirty years, as I note in the preface to Legal Foundations of a Free Society, except for a couple of areas that I explicitly call out, and for some matters of terminology and usage:

In one case I now disagree with something I originally wrote; I retained the original text and added an explanatory note (chapter 13, Part III.C). And in chapter 9 (Part III.C), I note that, regarding my earlier criticism of Rothbard’s argument for inalienability: “I now think it is possible that his approach is more compatible with my own than I originally realized.” But otherwise, I today still stand by most of the original content of those articles, in terms of substance. However, as noted several places in the text, I often now use terminology somewhat differently, e.g., the term state instead of governmentrivalrous or “conflictable” instead of scarce; using the word property to refer to the relation between humans with respect to owned resources, instead of referring to the owned resource itself, and so on. “I have in some cases updated the text to my current, preferred usage, but not always since it would have been too drastic and tedious.

As for the change of mind indicated above, ch. 13, “Legislation and the Discovery of Law in a Free Society,” as my Introductory Note to Part III.C explains, “In this section (Part III.C), I relied heavily on Bruno Leoni’s interpretation of Mises’s and Hayek’s views on the economic calculation problem and his related criticism of legislation by analogy to central economic planning. Subsequently, I gained a deeper understanding of the difference between Mises’s and Hayek’s approach to this issue, after Joseph Salerno initiated the “dehomogenization” debate.” 1

But earlier in my development I did change my mind or modify my views on several issues, and in the ensuing years on some applications. Here are a few, in roughly chronological order:

  • God. I initially was strongly Catholic, having been reared that way and attending 12 years of Catholic school, serving as an altar boy, and so on. When I was around 14 or 15 I started to develop serious doubts and soon became a die-hard atheist. I have not changed my view but I have become less militant and less hostile to religion, as I see now that it necessarily encodes and encapsulates much practical wisdom, and is preferable to the modern religion of statism and state worship.
  •  Anarchy. Initially a fairly orthodox Objectivist (starting around 10th grade in high school) and thus minarchist and hostile to anarchy, by law school I was a full-fledged Rothbardian anarcho-capitalist (though I prefer the term anarcho-libertarian now). See Then and Now: From Randian Minarchist to Austro-Anarcho-Libertarian.
  • Intellectual Property. Initially I assumed IP must be legitimate but was dissatisfied with arguments for it, when I decided to switch, as a young attorney, from oil & gas law to patent law in 1993 or so, I turned my attention to this issue and tried to come up with a better justification. The result was my complete change of mind and rejection of all forms of IP.
  • Abortion. Initially pro-choice on Objectivist and libertarian grounds, I for a long time held the view that early-term fetuses don’t have rights, late-term fetuses probably do, and thus only late term abortion should be prohibited. My view has only changed a bit here: first, after becoming a parent, I started to feel more strongly that even early-term abortion is usually immoral, even if it’s not murder; and now, I believe it should not be outlawed even in the later term, at least not by the criminal law of any external legal system. (see KOL443)
  • Rothbard’s Argument for Inalienability. I originally criticized Rothbard’s argument for inalienability. With a deeper understanding for the argument for self-ownership, based on the work of Hoppe and my own work, and thus for the argument for inalienability and against voluntary slavery contracts, I think Rothbard’s argument is basically correct, even if it’s incomplete and fairly sketchy, or that at least this is one way to construe it (even if his own view of contract and “implicit theft” and debtor’s prison is incompatible with his inalienability views). See LFFS, “A Libertarian Theory of Contract: Title Transfer, Binding Promises, and Inalienability,” Part III.C.1; see also “The Title-Transfer Theory of Contract.”
  • Israel. I was always strongly Israel, having written an embarrassing Randian-style defense in college, 2 and a controversial article on LewRockwell arguing for moving Israel to Utah, 3, but arguments in light of the recent Israel-Gaza conflict, by Hans Hoppe, Saifedean Ammous, and others 4, and getting more educated on the history of Israel, have made me reevaluate some my views. At this point I feel like my heart is with Israel, but my head recognizes what Israel has done and is doing cannot be justified.
  • Ukraine. I still despise the commies and think Russia is in violation of international law and evil, and I still do not believe NATO is an actual threat to Russia 5 and I believe Ukraine has the right to join NATO and the EU, but my view on this has been softened by the anti-war types and Hoppe’s comments. 6
  • Immigration. Not sure exactly if I’ve changed my mind but my position is more nuanced now, influenced by Hoppe’s immigration views. See I’m Pro-Immigration and Pro-Open Borders; On “Unowned” State Property, Legal Positivism, Ownership vs. Possession, Immigration, Public Roads, and the Bum in the Library; “A Simple Libertarian Argument Against Unrestricted Immigration and Open Borders.”
  1.  Knowledge vs. Calculation, Mises Blog (July 11, 2006) .[]
  2. Column: Israel: Victim of Bloodlust in Middle East?, LSU Daily Reveille, June 21, 1988. []
  3.  “New Israel: A Win-Win-Win Proposal,” LewRockwell.com (October 1, 2001). []
  4. Saifedean’s podcast; debate with Walter Block; debate with Yaron Brook; discussion with Jeremy Hammond; interview with Robert Breedlove; Hans-Hermann Hoppe, An Open Letter to Walter E. Block. []
  5. International Law, Libertarian Principles, and the Russia-Ukraine War. []
  6. The War in the Ukraine in Libertarian Perspective,” LewRockwell.com (PFS 2023; Sept. 28, 2023). []
Share
{ 0 comments }

This is a followup to comments on KOL418 | Corporations, Limited Liability, and the Title Transfer Theory of Contract, with Jeff Barr: Part II.

For more on this, see Stephan Kinsella, “The Title-Transfer Theory of Contract,” Papian Press Working Paper #1 (Sep. 7, 2024) and “A Libertarian Theory of Contract: Title Transfer, Binding Promises, and Inalienability,” chap. 9 of Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston: Papinian Press, 2023).

Brian‘s comment on KOL418: [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

Hoppe A Life in Liberty, cover

A Life in Liberty: Liber Amicorum in Honor of Hans-Hermann Hoppe was published today, Sep. 21, 2024, at the 2024 Annual Meeting of the Property and Freedom Society, in Bodrum, Turkey. More information here.

Some photos from the ceremony announcing the book are below.

Share
{ 1 comment }

Memories of Meeting Rothbard in 1994

Rothbard Man Economy and State inscription Kinsella[Update: see various biographical pieces on my publications page, including Alan D. Bergman, Adopting Liberty: The Stephan Kinsella Story (2025).]

As I recounted in “How I Became a Libertarian,” in Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023), I was fortunate to meet Murray Rothbard before he died, in October 1994 at the John Randolph Club meeting near Washington, D.C, where he autographed by copy of Man, Economy, and State: “To Stephan: For Man & Economy, and against the state –Best regards, Murray Rothbard.” 1

I had forgotten some of details of that trip but just came across a letter to a former law school classmate from 1996 which has some details about my first meeting with Rothbard, Hoppe, et al. Here is an edited excerpt: [continue reading…]

  1. I mention this also in The Genesis of Estoppel: My Libertarian Rights Theory. []
Share
{ 0 comments }

Libertarian Projects in 1995

[Update: see various biographical pieces on my publications page, including Alan D. Bergman, Adopting Liberty: The Stephan Kinsella Story (2025).]

In the Preface to Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023 [LFFS]), which contains updated articles published over a nearly 30 year period from 1994 to 2023, I noted that

Although the chapters were all written separately and at different times over three decades, many of them build on (or anticipated) others. For example, in chapter 10, originally published 1998–99, I outlined a sketch of a view of contracts, inalienability, and so on (note 48), and wrote “Elaboration of these ideas will have to await a subsequent article.” I did so in 2003, in the article which became chapter 9. Thus, I was able to piece together several articles in a fairly systematic form since they either built on or anticipated each other and were written to be consistent with each other and all flowing from the same core principles and reasoning.

Thus, my book contains chapters that build and refer to each other even if they were written years apart. [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

Preface and Acknowledgments to Legal Foundations of a Free Society

This is my Preface and Acknowledgments to Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023); see also Hoppe’s Foreword.

Preface: Legal Foundations of a Free Society

The issue of what property rights we have, or should have, what laws are just and proper, has long confronted mankind, and continues to be the subject of debate today. This book seeks to address these issues, with an approach that keeps in mind the nature and reality of human life—that we are purposeful human actors living in a world of scarcity and facing the possibility of interpersonal conflict—and the purpose of law and property norms: to enable us to live together, in society, peacefully and cooperatively. The goal is to vindicate the private law as developed in the decentralized systems of the Roman and common law, with an emphasis on consistency, principle, and the inviolable rights of the individual. In short, to argue for a private law system informed by libertarian principles. [continue reading…]

Share
{ 3 comments }

Fake Kinsella Article on Argumentation Ethics

A tweet alerted me to an alleged Portuguese translation of one of my articles, “Ética Argumentativa: Algumas Notas Breves Sobre o Conceito.”

Ética Argumentativa: Algumas Notas Breves Sobre o Conceito

I asked what this was a translation of and they sent me the below to an old “Mises Wire” piece allegedly authored by me. However I have never seen this, I did not write it, and it is oddly worded, as if it was written by a Russian bot and/or written in a foreign language and then auto-translated. I have no idea how this got posted at Mises.org under my name, but it’s not mine.

Update: It appears now it was written by Juan Carpio, and somehow my name got attached to it by mistake.
[continue reading…]

Share
{ 1 comment }

Below is the first second third draft of a working paper published under the Papinian Press Working Papers series. I expect a version of this to be published next year in David Howden, ed., Palgrave Handbook of Misesian Austrian Economics (Palgrave, forthcoming 2025), as part of the Palgrave Studies in Austrian Economics Book series. The working paper text is below and the PDFs of three drafts 1.8, 1.11, and 1.13. As noted below, “A Libertarian Theory of Contract: Title Transfer, Binding Promises, and Inalienability,” chap. 9 of Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston: Papinian Press, 2023), contains a more detailed presentation of some of the issues discussed here, although this paper includes additional arguments not explicitly made there.

(BTW I was asked to use the inline-citation format for references for this piece, instead of my preferred modified-Chicago/footnotes format, and I think the cluttered way references look in-line here is an illustration of why I despise this format.)

For more on the theory of contract, see my chapters “A Libertarian Theory of Contract: Title Transfer, Binding Promises, and Inalienability,” “Inalienability and Punishment: A Reply to George Smith,” and “Selling Does Not Imply Ownership, and Vice-Versa: A Dissection,” in Legal Foundations of a Free Society, and the following talks or interviews:

Errata: Add footnote 11 to the end of the section entitled “Implicit Theft”:

11. Interestingly, elsewhere Rothbard (2009, ch. 10, §7) again employs the concept of “implicit theft” in criticizing patent law: “Patents prevent a man from using his invention even though all the property is his and he has not stolen the invention, either explicitly or implicitly, from the first inventor.” “Inventions” are not ownable, scarce resources (they are designs, recipes, processes, not physical objects), and so cannot be “owned,” and thus cannot be stolen, so this reasoning is a bit confused, and, in any case, the concept of “implicit theft” makes no sense. Rothbard’s confusion on this issue also led him to support a type of patent (and copyright) by contract. See Kinsella (2008, the section “Contract vs. Reserved Rights,” and 2023h, n.46), and note 3, above.

Update: Penner seems to have a theory of contractual title transfer, based on abandonment, license, and possession, similar to mine. See Penner on Intellectual Property, Monopolies, and Property, pp. 79–85, et pass., in particular pp. 84–85:

The elaboration of transfer from abandonment proceeds as follows. An owner may abandon his property at any time and in any place (if it is movable) [SK’s note: this should apply only to ownable resources other than one’s body. It also should apply to immovables. This distinction is arbitrary.] that he likes. At the time and place of the abandonment, any person who takes possession of it gains a title in it. Since abandonment is entirely up to an owner, he can mark his abandonment of a thing by communicating it to others. It is now apparent that, should anyone wish to pass his title to anyone else, all he must do is abandon it to him in circumstances where that other is well placed to take possession of it. This can indeed be assured by licensing that other person to take possession of it, and then abandon it while he has it in his possession. ‘Take this: it’s yours‘. The common law has recognized the taking of possession as essential to the transfer of title in various ways, in the delivery of chattels, for example, or in the ancient common law ritual of ‘livery of seisin’, in which the transferor of land picked up a piece of the earth and placed it in the hand of the transferee before witnesses. The concept of this directional abandonment is reflected most clearly in linguistic use when we say that a person leaves his property to someone in his will.

Update: See also On Property Rights in Superabundant Bananas and Property Rights as Normative Support for Possession

See also errata for Legal Foundations of a Free Society:

Regarding ch. 9, and also “The Title-Transfer Theory of Contract”: see Williamson M. Evers, “The Law of Omissions and Neglect of Children,” J. Libertarian Stud. 2, no. 1 (1978): 1–10. He writes (p. 5): “A third legally enforceable duty has been contractual obligations. The present author, however, has maintained elsewhere that the only properly enforceable contracts are those in which transfers of property title have been agreed upon. Mere promises or induced expectations should not be legally binding; only the agreed-upon transfers of property.” This implicitly recognizes the notion, as I write in ch. 9 (217, 223), that contracts need not be viewed as binding obligations, and also the related notion that breach of contract is impossible (p. 209).

[continue reading…]

Share
{ 11 comments }

Free Epub of Legal Foundations of a Free Society Released

I published Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023) last September, in hardcover, soft cover, and Kindle formats. A free pdf was released at the time of publication as well and the book was published under at CC0 (no rights reserved) license.

A second printing, with corrections of accumulated errata, has just been released (August 2024; no change to pagination). A free epub file, including all errata corrected to date, is now available for download as well.

Share
{ 1 comment }

Reply to a Crank

As readers of my work know, I am usually very patient with sincere questions from newbs. But sometimes I reach my limit.

I received this email, unsolicited, from some guy I apparently made the mistake of replying to before, thus apparently encouraging and emboldening him. I’ll share my reply to him below. I’m so tired of these losers/cranks besieging me. [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

Libertarian Answer Man: Dueling, Stalking, Restraining Orders

A friend of mine, let’s call him “Gene,” asked me for my take on dueling and some related issues. This was in response to one of his friends criticizing libertarianism because it would have all kinds of unacceptable or unpleasant things such as frequent resort to dueling. Presumably the friend would outlaw dueling, and thinks libertarianism is defective because it would not.

My friend asked me if I thought dueling would be legal in a libertarian world, and also whether someone repeatedly harassing you and challenging you to a duel, not taking no for an answer, could be seen as making a threat. In that case, could the target/victim of this harassment seek an injunction or restraining order to keep harasser away. [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

I was long friends with Tibor Machan (see Remembering Tibor Machan, Libertarian Mentor and Friend: Reflections on a Giant). We corresponded for years and met many times in Auburn when I would attend Mises Institute events. When I lived in Philadelphia, from 1994–97, we would occasionally get together when he was passing through. As I recall, he introduced me one time to Patrick Burke. I think we had lunch together. Burke was a nice and gentle man, from what I dimly recall, a religion professor at Temple in Philly. He has apparently passed away in the meantime, as has Tibor.

In any case, I read his book No Harm: Ethical Principles for a Free Market (1994), which had just been published and which we had discussed at  lunch. It was decent but flawed, if earnest. I published a critical review of it in Tibor’s journal Reason Papers in 1995, Stephan Kinsella, “Book Review of Patrick Burke, No Harm: Ethical Principles for a Free Market (1994),” Reason Papers No. 20 (Fall 1995), p. 135 (see text below). Ultimate I critique his “harm” criterion, just as I critique a similar the similar approach opposing “imposing costs” on others by J.C. (Jan) Lester in his book Escape from Leviathan: Libertarianism without Justificationism.

See, e.g,. Stephan Kinsella, “A Libertarian Theory of Punishment and Rights,” in Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023) (LFFS), n.16 and accompanying text; idem, “Dialogical Arguments for Libertarian Rights,” in LFFS, at n.3 and accompanying text; idem, “‘Aggression’ versus ‘Harm’ in Libertarianism,” Mises Economics Blog (Dec. 16, 2009); and idem, “Hoppe on Property Rights in Physical Integrity vs Value,” StephanKinsella.com (June 12, 2011).

Burke’s focus on “harm” as the key principle behind rights, instead of aggression, leads him into error, for example accepting the legitimacy of blackmail and defamation law, and even laws banning dueling, since “a challenge to a duel is akin to blackmail.” His view of contracts is also flawed since it is based on the notion of detrimental reliance (which I critique in “A Libertarian Theory of Contract: Title Transfer, Binding Promises, and Inalienability,” in LFFS, at Part I.E).

No Harm: Ethical Principles for a Free Market*

T. Patrick Burke

Justifications in support of liberty are plentiful and diverse. This is to be expected, if the libertarian ideals of free minds and free markets are true, valid principles. For if liberty is justifiable, it is only natural that libertarian principles should be supported by many different lines of reasoning, including pragmatic, utilitarian, consequentialist, rationalist, and natural-law arguments, as well as by intuition, tradition, and common sense. Each time someone comes up with another insight into why freedom works, it adds to the argumentative evidence that individual freedom is a good thing. Patrick Burke in No Harm: Ethical Principles for a Free Market contributes to this libertarian corpus and offers yet another vantage point from which to view the virtues of freedom.

Burke’s clearly libertarian thesis is that “social justice requires market freedom.” (p.9) No Harm presents a justification of this thesis with an extended discussion of a rather simple core idea: that those who have not caused harm have a right not to be harmed Libertarians will recognize the No Harm principle as a close cousin of the non-aggression principle which prohibits the initiation of force.

In attempting to establish the No Harm principle underpinning the case for liberty and free markets, Burke does not offer a completely rigorous argument in the manner of some other libertarian theorists. Rather, he takes many things for granted, such as his position that human beings ought not to be harmed against their will, unless they have caused harm (discussed further below). Many of the premises Burke takes as true are accepted by most libertarians as well as by most ordinary people, so any conclusions he bases on these premises are still valuable. Other conclusions that Burke reaches, however, seem incorrect, perhaps because some of his foundations are not adequately defined and justified.

Before discussing the substance of the book, let me briefly make a comment about the book’s format. No Harm unfortunately contains endnotes rather than footnotes. Although some readers are annoyed by notes at the bottom of every page that “run along, like little angry dogs barking at the text,”1 in my opinion footnotes are much more convenient to glance at than endnotes, and are thus vastly superior. It is a wonder to me that anyone in this age of computerized word processing would ever use endnotes. (I realize that the use of endnotes in books is still common, however, and I also realize that this very review utilizes endnotes rather than footnotes, but I can only plead that any blame for this lies with the editor.) No Harm also contains no detailed table of contents, i.e., one listing subsections as well as chapter headings in hierarchical form. I find that a detailed table of contents, often used in legal treatises in addition to a shorter “summary of contents,” is very helpful in understanding in outline form the conceptual organization of the ideas laid out in the book, and in looking up desired topics. But enough of this procedural quibbling and on to the substance.

Punishment and Harm

In order to establish his case for the free market, Burke attempts to show three things: (1) that those who have not caused harm have a right to not be harmed; (2) that typical market activities do not cause harm; and (3) that governmental actions which proscribe such market activities do cause harm. Libertarians would probably agree with the general thrust of these three points, if “harm” is defined as the initiation or use of force. Indeed, point (1) resembles the libertarian non-aggression principle, under which an individual has a right to do anything unless it involves the initiation of (physical) violence, i.e., aggression or coercion. Building on the non-aggression principle, libertarians can fairly easily show that market transactions, since they do not involve coercion, are not rights-violative; and that governmental laws directed at such market actions are thus themselves coercive and illegitimate. The problem that libertarians typically face is justifying the claim that the only fundamental individual right is a right to not be coerced.

Burke wants to approach this problem from a slightly different angle, by focusing on the perhaps more intuitive or more general concept of “harm” rather than solely on the concept of physical violence or aggression. Thus, instead of arguing in favor of the non-aggression principle, Burke attempts to establish that those who have not caused harm have a right to not be harmed. I must admit that I found parts of the structure and organization of Burke’s argument somewhat hard to follow. Not until chapter 5 does he really tackle what “Causing Harm” is, and not until the last three chapters, 7, 8, and 9, does he explore his “Principle of No Harm” in detail. Further, many of side-points seem clearly wrong, as I will discuss in more detail below.

In the very beginning of and throughout his discussion, Burke implicitly equates the right to not be harmed with a right to not be punished, and thus he implicitly equates harm with punishment. (p.10) Thus, to establish his point (1) (those who have not caused harm have a right to not be punished), Burke must define harm and its causation, and must also explain when punishment is deserved or justified. Regarding harm, Burke maintains that to cause harm to a person by some action, he must be “worse off’ after the action than he was before, and the action in question must have “caused” the deterioration in condition. (p.46) Burke’s conception of harm and causation are not very controversial, but do not get one very far, either, in terms of normative rights theory, since at this stage they are merely descriptive, not normative or prescriptive.

The big question that Burke must answer is “Who ought to be punished?” Burke says, “The only just answer to this question can be: those who deserve punishment.” (p.40) Even this formulation is almost tautologically true: only people who “deserve” punishment “ought” to be punished (and vice-versa). Burke’s first really synthetic proposition is the claim that only those that have caused harm deserve to be punished. In support of this contention, Burke offers three related principles of “No Harm”. The first principle, the Principle of No Harm, states that human beings ought not to be harmed against their will, unless they have caused harm. According to the Principle of No Hann II, those who deliberately cause harm to the innocent deserve to be punished proportionately. Under the Principle of No Harm III, those who do not cause harm deliberately ought not to be punished. (Chs. 7, 8, 9)

Admittedly, if the tripartite Principle of No Harm is accepted as valid, then the rest of Burke’s argument falls into place: by the Principle ofNo Harm, we may punish people only if they have caused harm; the enforcement of any law is a use of punishment and laws may thus not be passed against those who do not cause hann; actions on the free market do not cause harm; and therefore, laws may not be passed that restrict economic liberties. Ultimately, though, Burke does not offer much defense of the Principle of No Harm, crucial as it is to his argument. Instead, Burke relies on its intuitive and widespread appeal. Burke writes:

Since the large majority of people accept the concept of crime, detest crime, and support legal punishment, in that sense and to that extent they already accept the Principle of No Harm. Causing harm would seem in fact to be the quintessence of what we mean by the notion of “morally wrong.” Anyone who wishes to cast doubt on this principle has the burden of coming up with an alternative theory as to the principle on which it is wrong to commit murder or robbery. [p.181]

Taking such fundamental rights for granted, it then becomes easy to validate the Principle of No Harm, if it

is simply an unpacking or explication of what is implicit in the elementary belief that it is wrong to kill or injure an innocent person  That actions such as murder and robbery are criminal and deserve punishment is one of the most fundamental moral intuitions of mankind, and one which has the strongest claim to acceptance on its own terms. We do not need a theoretical construction to tell us that it is valid. Although theoretical considerations may be useful in clarifying this insight, as they can also muddy it, any moral theory we develop must assume its essential validity and be dependent on it. [p.182, emphasis added]

Even though Burke believes that all this is self-evident, he offers some perceptive “theoretical reflections which can lend support to the principle.” (p.182) He eschews utilitarian and egoistic theories, because these “kinds of arguments, if indulged in exclusively, would have the effect of reducing the Principle of No Harm to nonmoral factors, …. which runs counter to our ordinary conception of morality.” Instead, Burke develops a Kantian position that focuses on man’s volition, his ability to make free choices. Because each person is a self-governor, the most fundamental moral obligation is not to deprive others, by physical force, of making free choices. “Coercion, the use of physical force to deprive an adult human being of the power of self-government, is intrinsically harmful and wrong, unless he has deserved it by causing harm to others.” (p.183, endnote omitted, emphasis added)

Burke’s derivation of a right not to be harmed is thus not completely rigorous, because he relies on “the most fundamental moral intuitions of mankind” and the like, rather than justifying these bedrock principles themselves. Nor does he adequately explain why these principles are self-evident, if they are. Burke’s conclusions are nevertheless insightful and largely convincing, because most of the assumptions he makes are shared by most civilized people anyway. Given his largely sound framework, Burke does a nice job of showing that market transactions do not usually cause “harm,” and thus ought not be “punished,” i.e., outlawed or regulated.

Harm versus Aggression

 I believe that Burke’s case could have been a stronger one if he had focused more on force rather than on harm, or if he had made his definition of harm more (explicitly and consistently) dependent on force. Such a refinement of his argument would also have helped him to avoid a few missteps along the way.

Much of Burke’s argument implicitly recognizes the crucial role of force in defining rights. When, for example, Burke argues that market transactions do not usually cause “harm,” he effectively characterizes harm as the inflicting of force on others. He also characterizes the right to not be harmed as a right to not be punished, thereby equating harm with punishment, i.e. force. It is when Burke views harm as the use of force that his discussion is most persuasive, which is not surprising to libertarians, who give force such a central role. Despite this implicit equation of force and harm in these contexts, however, Burke would not appear to agree with a general equation of harm with coercion, of rights-violations with the initiation of force. For instance, Burke maintains that rights-vio­ lations are not the only circumstances in which a person can be “harmed” (p.194); and that violence is not the only way to harm someone (see, e.g., his views on blackmail (p.57), defamation (p.57), and “dueling” (p.192), discussed further below). But punishment, after all, a central concept for Burke, is not merely the causing of “harm”—it is specifically the application of force to an individual. Why does Burke focus on (physical) punishment so much, if the physical, forcible element does not necessarily need to be part of the concept of harm? Why does Burke equate a right to not be harmed with a right to not be punished, but not harm with force in the general case?

A more rigorous and consistent case may be made for liberty if the interrelationship between harm, force, rights, and punishment is made clear. Under the libertarian non-ag­ gression principle, an individual has a right to do anything other than initiate force against others; thus punishment (the use of retaliatory force) is justified only in response to aggression, and never in response to harm alone.2 That is, the only punishable harm is one caused by an initiation of force. Burke’s concept of punishable harm as being broader than the mere initiation of force leads him to untrue conclusions in a few instances. First, if rights-violations or the initiation of force are not the only way that individuals are harmed (such that punishment may be visited upon the harmer), then it would follow that at least some harmful acts which are not rights-violations or violent can be legitimately punished. But if harm can follow from a non-coercive action, then this opens the door to regulate market activity, for while voluntary market activity does not involve coercion, how are we to say that it never causes “harm,” if harm can include non-coercive harm? Certainly the market, while indeed non-coercive, has many other features (e.g., it may be vulgar, crass, or amoral), and I can see no reason, and Burke offers none, that “non-coercive harm” (that nevertheless justifies punishment) is not among them.

As Burke states,

It does not make sense to believe that a person may cause hann to another by engaging in a market exchange with him. It does not make sense to believe that even when there is no question of force or fraud, a seller may cause harm to a buyer by selling him something which he requests to buy, and an employer may cause harm to an employee by giving him a job which he applies for. [p.42]

Burke also emphasizes that “The question of law is always a question of punishment.” (p.58) As Burke seems to recognize in these comments, the element of force cannot be left out of a viable definition of harm, if “harm” is to be used to justify (forcible) punishment. Any law will direct the use of physical force against certain individuals. Burke is correct that this is a type of “harm,” and may be legitimately inflicted on others when they, too, have banned someone. But the symmetry of the argument requires that the type of “harm” being punished involve force itself. If force is to be inflicted on others, surely this can only be justified when it is in response to an initial use of force. If A merely causes “harm” to B but without inflicting force (i.e., a non-coercive type of harm), B is indeed justified in causing “harm” to A in response – but only a non-force-inflicting type of harm, and thus certainly not punishment, which necessarily involves force.3 Thus, the only sort of harm that can legitimately be punished is force-inflicting(i.e., rights-violating) harm.

If Burke must resort to the concept of physical force to get useful results from his “harm” principle, one wonders why his thesis focuses on harm rather than on force simpliciter. Burke would do better to substitute the initiation of force for harm, and seek to establish: (l’) that those who have not initiated force have a right to not have force used against them; (2′) that typical market activities do not involve the initiation of force; and (3′) that governmental actions which proscribe such market activities do initiate force. In establishing step (l’) characterized this way, it is indeed relevant to ask, “Who deserves punishment?”, since punishment, like step (l’), focuses on the use of force itself. When these issues are clarified in this way, however, it becomes clear that the vague concept of “harm” is too broad to sufficiently justify rights and market transactions.

Further Problems

Burke’s view of the concepts of harm, force, rights, and punishment causes further difficulties. For example, consider Burke’s view on blackmail. Burke considers the case of the blackmailer offering to “not to publish compromising photographs of a man with his mistress if he will pay $500.” (p.57). Disagreeing with libertarians such as Rothbard, Burke maintains that “To blackmail a person is to threaten to cause him harm. Harm is not restricted to violence or the threat of it, but includes injury to a person’s reputation by defamation, libel and slander.” (p.57, endnote omitted, emphasis omitted) Burke here cites Pennsylvania’s criminal code regarding theft by extortion, presumably as an example, but hopefully not as a justification, for surely the mere existence of a positive state law cannot justify such a law. But Burke’s reasoning is too skimpy here, and he does not provide an argument showing why (punishable) harm includes defamation, libel, and slander.4 The mere uttering of sounds or words does not inflict force on others, and thus simply cannot justify retaliatory force against the utterer. Burke even recognizes this in another context: “A mere statement of a belief cannot in principle be harmful to anybody, even if it mistaken, since it always rests within the power of the listener whether he is to believe it or not.” (p.213)

For the same reason that we have a right to free speechs words cannot aggress against libel and slander laws cannot be tolerated in a free society. The only rights that exist, in my opinion, are rights to tangible, corporeal, property. This is because the only reason for property rights is to assign ownership to scarce resources, and only physical property can be scarce.5 Ideas and reputations are mere abstractions and are not property.6 Burke also believes that “a challenge to a duel is akin to blackmail.” (p.192; see also p.268 n.15) The argument here is very sketchy and, I believe, unconvincing.

Burke’s view on contracts is also problematic. In attempting to justify the “enforce­ ability” of contracts, Burke draws on the traditional legal concept of detrimental reliance. According to this theory,

The binding force of the contract comes from the fact that it leads each party justifiably to expect a certain perfonnance from the other and to rely upon that expectation in such a way that if the other fails to perfonn, then the first party is harmed. [p.71]

As others have pointed out, this reasoning is circular, for reliance on performance is not “reasonable” or justifiable unless one already knows that the promise is enforceable, which begs the question.7 What has not been widely recognized even by many libertarians is the fact that the enforcement of promises also violates freedom of speech: if I merely utter words (e.g., “I promise to do X”) then I have not used force against you; thus you are not justified in using force against me to “enforce” the contract. Contracts may legitimately be construed only as conditional transfers or exchanges of property.8

Burke also offers the Principle of Double Effect as a way to determine whether we may outlaw an action that will have both bad and good effects. Burke submits the example of a terrorist who is threatening to kill a hostage unless certain demands are met:

A police sharpshooter could perhaps shoot the terrorist, but there is a risk that he might shoot the hostage by mistake. Is it morally pennissible for him to try to shoot the terrorist?

The Principle of Double Effect answers this question by providing three criteria:

  1. The evil effect must not be the cause of the good effect. This rule is necessary because the end does not justify the We may not do harm in order that good may come of it.
  2. The evil effect must not be deliberately
  3. The harm caused must not be greater than the harm prevented, or the good done. [p.198]

There are many problems with these criteria. For example, how in the world do you weigh harms against one another, or the harm caused against the good intended? A more serious problem with this principle is that Burke simply asserts it as if it is true, without offering any justification for it, evidently relying on its somewhat intuitive appeal.

In the area of economics, Burke admirably rejects antitrust laws, but seems to accept the concept of monopoly nonetheless. “If a genuine monopoly is achieved in an industry, and the monopolist firm raises prices above the competitive level, it creates an incentive for other firms to enter the industry in competition with it.” (p.80) This ignores, however, Rothbard’s demonstration that the very concept of free-market monopoly is invalid.

Burke’s views on the Great Depression are baffling. He recognizes that the Great Depression was, contrary to popular belief, caused by actions of the federal government. So far, so good. According to Austrian economic theory, recessions and depressions are caused when the malinvestments of artificial booms, caused by inflation of the money supply, are liquidated. Thus, it is a federally-controlled decrease in interest rates, or the corresponding expansion of the money supply, that causes depressions.10 Burke, however, maintains that one of the actions of the federal government that caused, or prolonged, the Great Depression “was the action of the Federal Reserve in increasing interest rates and further restricting the money supply, precisely at the time when just the opposite action was needed.” (p.91, emphasis added; see also pp.33,164) The “opposite action” that Burke believes was “needed”—i.e., inflation of the money supply – is the very type of thing that caused the Great Depression. Only Milton Friedman is cited here; apparently Burke is unfamiliar with the Austrian work on the business cycle, or finds it not worth taking into account in his analysis.11

In another economic misstatement, Burke says that “Far from causing harm, the seller who raises his prices in a shortage is doing just what needs to be done to reduce the shortage, he is providing an incentive for producers to produce more.” (p.95) But it seems to me that this is untrue: the raised prices provide a disincentive to prospective buyers with less urgent needs from purchasing the goods.12

Burke’s favorable comments regarding democracy are also somewhat naive, or at least paint too rosy a picture regarding the virtues of democracy. He maintains that representative government is an “effectual system,” and that “The idea of democracy is enshrined in two principles: majority rule, and human rights. Both of these, but especially human rights, are antipathetic to authoritarianism.” (p.23) He also maintains that “democ­ racy is the most effective means of ensuring the protection of human rights against government” (p.163), and he has “no doubt that representative democracy is the best and wisest form of government where it is capable of existing”. (p.234) Burke’s use of phrase “human rights” rather than “individual rights” is somewhat unsettling, because the term “human rights,” like the term “liberal” in American usage, has acquired a leftist or socialist tinge.13 Further, majority rule as a principle can resolve into mob rule, which is unlikely to favor individual rights. Indeed, democracy has systemic features which make it tend to oppress liberty.14 Democracy is not as benevolent and compatible with the free market at Burke assumes.

Useful Insights

All this is not to say that Burke does not make many perceptive points in No Harm. Although his Principle ofNo Harm could stand some refinement and is not defended with complete rigor, it is, after all, true that people should not “harm” one another, and most decent people do agree with this, stated as a general proposition. Burke has many good explanations that show why, contrary to popular wisdom, we are not harmed by market transactions, and are, conversely, harmed by government intervention. Probably the most praiseworthy aspect of Burke’s book is his extended discussion of the “harmlessness” of voluntary market transactions.

There are many fresh insights sprinkled throughout the text. One useful insight of Burke’s that had never occurred to me regards the typical leftist assertions that “the actions of a person in economic distress are not free.” (p.49) Liberals typically maintain that a person in danger of starvation is “compelled by circumstances” to accept a low-wage, dangerous, or otherwise undesirable job. As Burke notes, this

is thought to be a significant question only because it is assumed that people in distress who accept tough conditions are being harmed. It is supposed to provide an explanation for what otherwise, on this interpretation, would be bizarre and incomprehensible behavior. Given that they are causing harm to themselves, what could explain such a paradoxical action, since presumably they are not masochists? The answer is made that they have no alternative, they are compelled to take the job. It is assumed that this explanation renders comprehensible an action which otherwise would make no sense. Where it is clear that a person is benefiting from an action, however, there is no urgent need to ask whether he does so freely. A penniless beggar given a lottery ticket which turned out to win him a million dollars would be under heavy economic and psychological pressure to accept the prize, but there would be little practical point in questioning whether his acceptance was truly free. [p.49, emphasis added]

Burke also notes that some writers oppose market freedom based on alleged “market failure.” For example, a car owner, who is often mechanically ignorant, may be taken advantage of by a mechanic, who has an incentive to lie and diagnose greater problems with the car than actually exist. Since the mechanic or service station owner is supposedly “rational” in this case, this may be a case of “market failure” requiring government regulation. Burke perceptively points out that:

To call lying a case of market failure betrays an elementary misunderstanding of the concept of a free market. Deliberate deception, or fraud, is not a part of the concept of a free market. It is certainly true that the successful operation of a market economy depends on maintaining ethical behavior, and there must be legal remedies available for people who have been defrauded. Fraud, however, is not a case of the failure of the market, but of the moral failure of individuals. [p.89]

Conclusion

 All in all, No Harm presents a fresh perspective on the virtues of liberty from the viewpoint of the ubiquitous concept of harm. Burke does a good job of explaining why, in general, people are not “harmed” in a free market, and thus free market activities should not be regulated by governments, whose job is to punish those who cause harm. However, Burke’s neglect of foundational issues, justifications, and precise definitions, and his unfortunate willingness to label some non-coercive actions as punishable harms, weaken his overall case, and cause him to stray into error on a few issues. Yet Burke does offer many useful insights, and is fundamentally correct in championing freedom and pointing out its many benefits. We should always cheer when yet another voice is added to the chorus crying for freedom.

N. Stephan Kinsella,

Schnader, Harrison, Segal & Lewis, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania

 

Endnotes

*Page references to this book will be given parenthetically in the text.

**The author practices computer software and hardware patent law with Schnader Harrison Segal & Lewis, in Philadelphia. He may be reached by internet at kin­sella@shsl.com.

  1. S.M. Crothers, “That History Should be Readable”, in The Gentle Reader 172 (1903; repr. 1972), quoted in Bryan A. Gamer, The Elements of Legal Style 92 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991).
  2. On the definition of “aggression” and the libertarian non-aggression principle, see Murray N. Rothbard, For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto (New York: Liber­ tarian Review Foundation, reprint ed., 1985), 23. See also Hans-Hermann Hoppe, A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism: Economics, Politics, and Ethics 139-41, 237 n.17 (Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989) (arguing that property rights protect the physical integrity of property, but not the value of property).
  3. See my articles “Estoppel: A New Justification for Individual Rights”, Reason Papers No. 17 (Fall 1992), p. 61, and “Punishment and Proportionality; the Estoppel Approach”, J. Libertarian Studies (forthcoming), for a theory focusing on this sort of symmetry.
  4. On the illegitimacy of libel and slander (defamation) laws, see Rothbard, supra note 2, at 96-97; idem, The Ethics of Liberty 126-27 (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1982) and Walter Block, Defending the Undefendab/e: The Pimp, Prostitute, Scab, Slumlord, Libeler, Moneylender, and Other Scapegoats in the Rogue’s Gallery of Ameri­ can Society (San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1991).
  5. For a discussion of the necessity of the concept of “scarcity” to a proper definition of goods or property, see Ludwig von Mises, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics 93, 235-36, 528 (Chicago: Contemporary Books, Inc., 3d rev’d ed. 1966); Murray N. Roth­ bard, 1 Man, Economy, and State: A Treatise on Economic Principles 4 (Los Angeles: Nash Publishing, 1962); and Hoppe, supra note 2, at 8-10, 134 et seq.
  6. On libel laws, see supra note 4. For a discussion of intellectual property rights, see Rothbard, supra note 2, at 123-24; idem, supra note 5, at 652-60; Tom G. Palmer, “Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified?” “The Philosophy of Property Rights and Ideal Objects,” 13 J. Law & Pub/. Poly 817 (1990), as well as other articles in same issue (No. 3, Summer 1990) and in Vol. 13, issue no. 1 (Winter 1990) of this journal; Tom G. Palmer, “Intellectual Property: A Non-Posnerian Law and Economics Approach11, 12 Hamline L. Rev. 261 (1989); Wendy J. Gordon, “An Inquiry into the Merits of Copyright: “The Challenges of Consistency, Consent, and Encouragement Theory”, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 1343 (1989).
  7. See, g., Randy E. Barnett,”A Consent Theory of Contract”, 86 Columbia L. Rev. 269, 274-76 (1986); Randy E. Barnett and Mary E. Becker, “Beyond Reliance: Promissory Estoppel, Contract Fonnalities, and Misrepresentation”, 15 Hofstra L. Rev. 443, 446-47, 452 (1987). For further discussion of these and related issues, see Williamson M. Evers, “Toward a Reformulation of the Law of Contracts”, 1 J. Libertarian Stud. 3 (1977); Randy Barnett, “Contract Remedies and Inalienable Rights”, 4 Social Phil. & Poly 179 (1986); Rothbard, supra note 4, chapter 19;
  8. For insightful discussions into the nature of contracts, see Evers, supra note 7; Rothbard, supra note 4, chapter 19, “Property Rights and the Theory of Contracts”; and Barnett, “A Consent Theory of Contract”, supra note 6. These formulations are not, however, without problems. I plan to discuss this issue at further length in a future article.
  9. Rothbard, supra note 5, at chapter 10, pp. 604-14; Hoppe, supra note 2, at chapter 9, esp.pp. 180-85.
  10. See Murray N. Rothbard, America’s Great Depression (Los Angeles: Nash Publishing, 2d 1972); idem, supra note 5, at ch. 12, 11; Mises, supra note 5, at ch. XX.
  11. In a discussion of the “business cycle,” Burke notes that the two chief explanations for this phenomenon are that it is due to excessive investment; or to governmental policies, such as “control of the money supply.” (p.94) Burke cites neither Mises’s nor Rothbard’s work on the Austrian theory of the business cycle. See supra note 10.
  12. See, g., Murray N. Rothbard, “Government and Hurricane Hugo: A Deadly Combi­nation,” in The Economics of Liberty at 137 (Auburn, Alabama: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1990) (first published in The Free Market, vol. 7, No. 12 (December 1989)); and George Reisman, The Government Against the Economy, ch. II, sec. 2, p. 42, et passim (Ottawa, Ill.: Jameson Books, 1979).
  13. See, g., the United Nation’s Universal Declaration of Human Rights, U.N. GAOR, 217A (III) (1948), at articles 22-26 (reciting, for example, human rights to “social security” and to “free” education).
  14. For perceptive articles discussing this point, see Hans-Hermann Hoppe, ‘Time Preference, Government, and the Process of De-Civilization From Monarchy to Democracy”, 5 des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines 319 (1994). Interestingly, Frank Knight made a similar point back in 1929. In his essay Freedom as Fact and Criterion, Knight stated:

We say that the victim of a highwayman is coerced, not because the character of his choice between the alternatives presented is different from any other choice, but because we think the robber does “wrong” in making the alternatives what they are.

In no other sense is it possible to speak of coercion. No human being can ever literally “force” another to do anything (though one may of course forcibly prevent another from acting)….[T]he threat of violence… as a means of controlling the conduct of a human being has only a figurative kinship with the action of a physical force in changing the state of rest or motion of a mass of matter. It is interesting to note that when conduct is influenced by an offer to improve one’s condition, instead of a threat of worsening it, we do not call it force or duress.

Frank H. Knight, Freedom and Reform: Essays in Economics and Social Philosophy 17 (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1982).

Share
{ 1 comment }

© 2012-2025 StephanKinsella.com CC0 To the extent possible under law, Stephan Kinsella has waived all copyright and related or neighboring rights to material on this Site, unless indicated otherwise. In the event the CC0 license is unenforceable a  Creative Commons License Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License is hereby granted.

-- Copyright notice by Blog Copyright