≡ Menu

Tariffs and Legal Uncertainty

[From my Webnote series]

Regarding various new or increased or changed tariffs being proposed by Trump: of course free trade is good and the US should unilaterally abolish tariffs. 1 (I seem to recall other arguments for unilateral free trade—perhaps by Mises, Rothbard, Hazlitt, Friedman—but cannot find them; if anyone recalls any of these please notify me.)

The uncertainty faced by businesses and actors in the US as a result of these changes is simply one consequence of the state having the very power to legislate. [continue reading…]

  1. On Trump’s recent tariffs, see Gigi Foster et al., Has Team Trump Blinked?. On unilateral free trade, see Ron Paul, “Free Trade and Protectionism,” in Llewellyn H. Rockwell, Jr., ed., The Free Market Reader (“Even if other countries maintain tariffs or subsidies, we would be helped, not hurt, by unilaterally ending ours.”); Laurence M. Vance, Why Libertarians Loathe Tariffs; Louis Rouanet, The Case for Unilateral Free Trade; Patrick Barron Unilateral Free Trade; Ryan McMaken, We Need Unilateral Free Trade with Post-Brexit Britain; Ryan McMaken, It’s Time for Unilateral Free Trade with Canada, Australia, New Zealand, and the UK; Louis Rouanet, Britain Should Embrace Unilateral Free Trade Right Now; Patrick Barron, Two Common Objections to Unilateral Free Trade. But see Jeffrey Tucker, “Does the Trade Deficit Matter?“; idem, The Discrediting of Free Trade. []
Share
{ 0 comments }

Concurrent Review and Judicial Supremacy

[From my Webnote series]

As noted in this Grok conversation, the US Supreme Court assumed the power to review legislation for constitutionality in Marbury vs. Madison—the power of judicial review. In this case, the Court was asked to issue a writ to place Marbury on a Court. The Court admitted he should be placed here but that the Judiciary Act of 1789, which seemed to give the Supreme Court original jurisdiction to issue such writs, was unconstitutional since it unconstitutionally expanded the Court’s original jurisdiction beyond what the Constitution specified. In other words, the Court appeared to decline a power but was only able to decline this power by assuming the power to review federal laws for constitutionality and declare them unconstitutional if found wanting.

We take this power of judicial review for granted now, but it was not so clear initially, and not all countries permit their courts to review legislation for constitutionality. However, this power quickly morphed into judicial supremacy—idea that only the judicial branch, in particular the Supreme Court, has the right, power, and obligation to pronounce legislation as unconstitutional; that what the Court says, goes: if the Court says a statute is constitutional, it is; if it says it’s not, it’s not. It’s up to the Court to decide this; not the other two branches.

But as I note in Judicial Activism and the Presumption of Unconstitutionality (draft, 2005), the theory of concurrent review makes more sense.:

Second, I agree with Jefferson’s theory of “concurrent review,” whereby each branch of the federal government (executive, legislative, judicial) has an equal right to determine the constitutionality of (federal) government action. Meaning the Supreme Court and the President can (and should) refuse to endorse or enforce a law it believes to be unconstitutional; Congressmen should refuse to vote for laws they believe to be unconstitutional, and so on. This is in contrast with the now-dominant doctrine of judicial supremacy, the idea that the Supreme Court is the sole and final arbiter of the Constitution and constitutionality. (On concurrent review, see David N. Mayer, The Constitutional Thought of Thomas Jefferson (University Press of Virginia, 1995), 131, 259, 263, 269-72; William J. Quirk & R. Randall Bridwell, Judicial Dictatorship, (Transaction Pub., 1995), xiv, 10-11, 13.)

But what this means is that the federal courts can “overturn” a federal law that they believe is unconstitutional by simply refusing to enforce it. This is because they are an intricate part of the very machinery of the federal government. If they refuse to go along with an unconstitutional law, it is essentially nullified. The same is true of the Presidency and the Congress–they can refuse as well.

In addition to concurrent review, which relates to the equal and independent obligation of each of the three branches of the federal government to refuse to enforce (or enact) an unconstitutional law, under federalist principles there is also vertical separation of powers in which the States also have a constitutional right to refuse to permit unconstitutional federal laws to be enforced in their territory (nullification), and/or to secede; the only remedy that the US Federal Government, or other States, has against a state that will not comply with federal law or even with the Constitution is to eject that State from the Union, much like a voluntary club or organization (a country club, NATO, the UN, the EU, and so on) and eject a member for not paying dues or not abiding by the organization’s rules.

See also this Grok conversation (excerpt):

The Jeffersonian Lens: Concurrent Review vs. Judicial Supremacy

To understand Trump’s move, consider the Jeffersonian theory of concurrent review, which holds that all three branches of government—executive, legislative, and judicial—share an equal obligation to uphold the Constitution. This contrasts with the notion of judicial supremacy, cemented by Marbury, where the Supreme Court positioned itself as the final arbiter of constitutional meaning. Thomas Jefferson and others warned against this, arguing that no branch should dominate the others in interpreting the Constitution. As legal scholars like David N. Mayer and William J. Quirk have noted, concurrent review empowers the executive to resist unconstitutional laws or delegations, even absent a court ruling.

Trump’s pushback against agency rulemaking aligns with this vision. If Congress has unconstitutionally delegated its legislative authority to agencies, the executive branch—under Trump’s leadership—has a duty to refuse to enforce or enable such overreach. This isn’t a power grab; it’s a reclamation of constitutional boundaries, leveraging the post-Chevron landscape where courts are now more likely to strike down agency actions lacking clear statutory backing.

Update: I would disagree with Richard Epstein too. See the transcript excerpts from Epstein on Roman Law:

John Yoo (3:42): As usual, Charlie, I agree with you about 75% of the way. The 25% is the fun part to talk about. And I’m so glad that you are willing to volunteer yourself as a second target at which Richard has to shoot, because as we keep moving, it’s a target-rich environment for him, but he can’t concentrate on more than one target at a time. So, you know, first I agree with you. In a way, it’s a technical issue of federal courts law. How far does the power of a court run in issuing a remedy? And I find that kind of boring. I think the answer is actually quite simple, which is that the Constitution says federal courts decide cases and controversies, and the cases or controversies are just the people who appear before you in the courtroom. And so that’s how far the judge’s power goes, is to the people who appear. But as you said though, it contains much more important structural issues about the Constitution, and of course it has the most immediate political effect of letting, of unleashing President Trump’s agenda from these nationwide injunctions and preventing any single district judge from stalling the federal government in its tracks. Although, as you said, Charlie, this means that the Supreme Court is going to have to intervene faster and earlier in cases like the birthright citizenship case or a lot of President Trump’s executive orders. But the really big structural issue, I think, is one that’s raised most sharply by Abraham Lincoln and Dred Scott. I don’t want to overclaim here, but remember that Abraham Lincoln was faced with this problem of a Supreme Court that believed in its own supremacy and thought that it should issue a decision, Dred Scott, that settled the rights of all freed or escaped slaves throughout the country. And remember Lincoln said, because, right, Lincoln’s a member, the leader of the Republican Party. Lincoln’s, the Republican Party is founded out of opposition to Dred Scott and rises to prominence and wins the 1860 election because it’s opposed to Dred Scott’s holding, which is that slavery cannot be stopped by Congress and the president or even the freed states. And Lincoln said this. He said, I will obey the last line of Dred Scott, which means Dred Scott himself has to be handed over back to his original owner. And then Lincoln says, “I have no obligation under the Constitution to obey that opinion.” And he says, “It’s an opinion of the Supreme Court, the logic of the Supreme Court, and apply to every other case in the country. All those other slave owners can sue by the millions to grab back freed slaves, but I’m not going to go out and find them and voluntarily hand them over.” That’s essentially the same position, I think, that President Trump and President Biden and all the other past presidents are taking. I will obey the order of the district judge, but as an independent branch of government with the right to interpret the Constitution, too, I don’t have to bend the knee to the Supreme Court’s interpretation everywhere else. And I think that’s the deeper structural decision that the Supreme Court made here in this Cassa case. But surely, before we go to Richard, surely the Supreme Court said that it has the capacity to issue nationwide injunctions. It does, but I don’t know whether a president doesn’t also have the authority to take. Now, Lincoln also said that you should only do this when the Supreme Court’s really wrong on an issue of major importance like slavery. And Lincoln also said, in general, I will obey the Supreme Court nationwide, because I think that’s their job and they might be better at it than me. But he also said we would be giving up our right to self-government if we let the Supreme Court decide finally for the whole country on the Constitution’s meaning.

Richard Epstein (7:39): Interesting. So Richard, how much of that do you agree with? Well, I’m trying to catch my breath, but go back from Dred Scott 100 years later to Brown v. Board of Education, and all of a sudden now the Court’s the good guy on segregation, not the bad guy. And the great question was whether or not you would say about Brown v. Board, it only applied to the parties that were there and that every other southern state was free to do what it wanted until they themselves were directly sued. And what we did is we had exactly the opposite result in a case called Cooper v. Aaron, which says when the Supreme Court talks, it’s going to be a form, not of judicial parity, which was what John was pushing, but rather a form of judicial supremacy, which was the way in which this thing started to work out, and I think, in effect, talking about a nationwide injunction is not the form you want in order to deal with that debate. I think that it is also the case that most of the people in this country have accepted the Cooper v. Aaron solution was done for about 1958 or so. And that that would be today the law of the land. Well, which do I believe? Well, let me put it this way. I believe that the branch which is correct ought to have the final say. The problem is we never agree as to which that branch turns out to be. And so in this particular case, I think that the word you used, Charles, to say we don’t want to allow some random judicial court to have the power over the case was wrong. The reason it’s wrong is that you use the word random. And when people are starting to bring suits with respect to these kinds of cases, the last thing that happens is that a plaintiff who has the choice of forum is going to randomly go into the telephone book and say, “Well, I think I’ll go to the central district of Idaho for this particular case.” There are huge strategic advantages to going to one place or the other, and that means that the plaintiff is going to have a huge advantage, which means that these nationwide injunctions are going to be skewed in one form or another, and so I think what happens is that the correct rule, which is the old English rule of equity, is that when you start to issue an injunction, you bind only the parties to the particular case, and you don’t bind third parties, and they will be bound, if at all, by a doctrine of precedent, which means that the case can be used elsewhere in the American system. If you do something in the Third Circuit, that’s not going to be binding on the judges in the Fourth Circuit. So that you’re going to have, essentially, the Supreme Court to resolve them. And the problem with John’s position is that if the Court itself does not have an authority to do this, and you have splits in the circuit, and you have a congressional ace in the hole or a presidential view, what’s going to happen next? And this is another problem we have. Donald Trump, as the president of the United States, has taken the single most aggressive position on the scope of executive power that I’ve ever seen anywhere. The most recent manifestation of that had to do with the TikTok case, where he said, “Well, Congress had passed a statute which surely relates to foreign commerce. But I’m the president, and I have exclusive control over foreign affairs, and so that statute is not binding on me.” Well, that’s a complete sort of revolution from taking place, and you have this inter-mural fight, and it seems to me that the only body that can resolve it is going to be the Supreme Court. It said some very silly things in some of the earlier cases, cut back on them in some later cases, but I’m afraid I still believe, unhappily, in the doctrine of judicial supremacy. Why is it an unhappy situation? Because it turns out, no matter where you put the ultimate power, there are going to be cases where you miserably reject the result. And so what you have to do is to project over the full range of cases to see which of these doctrines is going to be least harmful. And in doing that, I think I come up with the Supreme Court for one very simple reason. We’re not in England, where parliamentary supremacy is unchallenged because you have one guy doing it. In the United States, you have a presidential system, and you have a federalism system. And if it turns out that the courts cannot resolve these problems, the inter-branch disputes that you’re going to see are going to be, to my mind, extremely dangerous. So I think that I thought the decision was right. I would want to decide it on somewhat narrower grounds. Anytime one wants to talk about 18th-century equity principles, that’s the stuff that I was raised on when I was a student doing law in England back in the 1960s. And so I’m very glad to see that they, I think, got that one right. I also think they were right not to say boo about the substantive merits of this particular case, which is going to be a titanic battle come the fall.

Share
{ 0 comments }

Beckmann, Hammer and TickleBy the late, great Petr Beckmann. On Amazon, and online here. “A collection of subversive jokes from the Soviet Union.”

Share
{ 0 comments }

Mises on God

[From my Webnote series]

See also:

[continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

A Tale of Two Legal Systems: Common Law and Statutory Law

Interesting article on Mises Wire: “A Tale of Two Legal Systems: Common Law and Statutory Laws,” by Ugo Stornaiolo S.:

It was the best of the laws, it was the worst of the laws, it was built on freedom, it was built on power, it was the spontaneous order of organic social institutions, it was the deliberate order of ideology and coercion, it was a stream of jurisprudence guiding us to justice, it was a tangle of statutes pushing us to restriction.

In short, law, either jurisprudence or legislation, can only be understood by comparison, and adapting the introduction of A Tale of Two Cities, we see two systems, common and civil law, and gaps in freedom between them.

Read more>>

He quotes my article “Legislation and Law in a Free Society.” See also the longer version, “Legislation and the Discovery of Law in a Free Society,” in Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023); and related comments from Hoppe, e.g. at n.152 of this chapter.

Share
{ 0 comments }

“All that is not permitted is forbidden”

[From my Webnote series]

Related

I recently had conversation with some fellow libertarians about how to interpret the governing rules of a given organization, and whether members of the group who receive information submitted to them are free to release this information publicly. I pointed out that the organization’s Bylaws don’t say we cannot release this information, to which someone else said it doesn’t say we can, either. I responded that the general rule is that we don’t live by permission; all that is not forbidden is permitted. In response, someone argued that this reasoning sounds like the excuse the state uses, for example when the US Government argues that its power is basically plenary, despite the enumerated powers structure of the Constitution and the Tenth Amendment, because of the interstate commerce clause in effect granting it broad legislative powers—an interpretation we libertarians usually criticize and reject. [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

Related:

Note: Some videos are now available, Professor Moreteau’s Youtube channel, including the keynote, below. See also the July 2025 issue of the Center for Civil Law Studies newsletter.

***

I’m attending what looks to be a fascinating legal conference next week, “The Louisiana Civil Code of 1825: Content, Influences and Languages; Past and Future,” LSU Law Center, March 20–21, 2025. 1 Somewhat to my surprise, I’m looking forward to it. Let me splain. (Note: I realize this post may come across as narcissistic or self-absorbed to some; I don’t care; in this case, it’s not for you. Some people are interested in this, others not. And one purpose of my blogging like this is to create posts that in effect can serve as searchable notes or “footnotes” for later use. 2 So avert thine eyes if you don’t like it…) [continue reading…]

  1. Steve Sanoski, “LSU Law hosting international legal conference to celebrate the Bicentennial of Louisiana Civil Code of 1825 on March 20-21,” LSU Law (March 11, 2025); program. []
  2. Blog Posts as Footnotes–Webnotes; Grok conversation. []
Share
{ 4 comments }

Petr Beckmann’s The Structure of Language

I just came across some correspondence with Bryan Garner from 1993, who is by now a well known expert on legal writing, style, and related matters. (His books include his first book, A Dictionary of Modern Legal Usage, and many others, such as Garner’s Modern English Usage, Black’s Law Dictionary, The Elements of Legal Style, etc.) I met Bryan when he conducted a legal writing seminar for new lawyers in my firm, Jackson Walker, in 1992, shortly after he founded is firm Lawprose. I corresponded with him a bit, in part about my upcoming article “A Civil Law to Common Law Dictionary,” La. L. Rev. 54 (1994), which I later turned into a book, Louisiana Civil Law Dictionary (2011).

When we met, I believe we discussed how there is redundancy in language, e.g., how you write on a check “$100” and “One hundred and no/100 dollars.” Some criticize this, but there is a reason for this redundancy. In my letter I noted: [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023) has been translated into Portuguese as Fundamentos Legais de uma Sociedade Livre (forthcoming 2025), by Rick Theu and VAP of the Instituto Hoppe (Brasil). The book has been divided into two voluments: Vol. 1 (Parts I–III; pdf) and Vol. 2 (Parts IV–VI; pdf).

According to the publisher (and as also noted in the Publishers note below), “there is still some revision to be done (some of the footnotes need to be corrected—some are referencing the wrong pages, some could reference the corresponding Portuguese edition of the works that have already been translated, etc.).” I will post updated files when received. I append below Hoppe’s Foreword and my Preface.

The Publisher’s note is included below. I wish to make one correction. They write “The work of translation is always thankless.” Not true: they have my gratitude and appreciation. 1 It is always a pleasure to encounter others with a passion to help spread the ideas of liberty. [continue reading…]

  1. I am reminded of my correspondence with the late, great Dr. Petr Beckmann in the 1990s (see various posts here). I had proposed writing a treatment of some of his ideas on nuclear power and asked his permission; he replied that I had not only his permission but his gratitude. Also, as I pointed out to the translators here: my comment above was more jocular—just an excuse to express gratitude. As I pointed out to him, in my 1994 review of Hoppe, jokingly wrote this: “18. Hoppe dedicates the volume to Murray N. Rothbard, stating that ‘words cannot express my personal gratitude.’ Economics and Ethics xi. Of course (I point out in jest), by using words to express his personal gratitude Hoppe contradicts himself by stating that words cannot express his gratitude.” I was being cheeky. I removed this comment from the version in my book … ch. 22 of Legal Foundations of a Free Society. []
Share
{ 0 comments }

New paper:  Łukasz Dominiak and Igor Wysocki, “Libertarianism, Defense of Property, and Absolute Rights,” Analiza i Egzystencja 61 (2023): 5–26. Abstract:

The present paper argues that libertarians (e.g. Murray Rothbard, Stephan Kinsella) who subscribe to the proportionality principle while embracing the view that to have a right to property is to have a right to defend it run into what we call the Property Defense Dilemma. For if the only way to defend property is to defend it disproportionately, then a private property right—contrary to what these thinkers claim—is not accompanied by a right to defend it. The most plausible way out of the dilemma—the present paper argues—is to conceive of private property rights as only weakly absolute, to use Matthew H. Kramer’s illuminating distinction. On the other hand, libertarians who, like Walter Block, would like to escape the dilemma by replacing the proportionality standard with the gentleness principle run into other sorts of problems (moral implausibility, incoherence), which also shows that it is the libertarian view on rights as infinitely stringent side constraints that calls for revision and attenuation.

[continue reading…]

Share
{ 2 comments }

Legal Foundations of a Free Society in Chinese

Stephan Kinsella’s Legal Foundations of a Free Society (Houston, Texas: Papinian Press, 2023) is now available in a Chinese translation as 自由社会的法律根基 (Feb. 2025) (pdf) (previous draft mentioned here). The proofread text of the translation is also available below.

The book was translated by Li San (李三) of the Mises Translation and Compilation Society (米塞斯编译社译丛), a group dedicated to translating and editing the classic works of the Austrian School.

As the Society is not licensed to publish, I plan to publish paper and kindle versions of this with Papinian Press. Stay tuned.

[continue reading…]

Share
{ 1 comment }

The Freedom Scale

The Freedom Scale, Christopher CookThere is apparently yet another new libertarianism-related book in the works: The Freedom Scale: An Accurate Measure of Left and Right, by one Christopher Cook, whom I have never heard of before (h/t Adam Haman). See:

My initial impressions from a quick glance: [continue reading…]

Share
{ 0 comments }

© 2012-2025 StephanKinsella.com CC0 To the extent possible under law, Stephan Kinsella has waived all copyright and related or neighboring rights to material on this Site, unless indicated otherwise. In the event the CC0 license is unenforceable a  Creative Commons License Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License is hereby granted.

-- Copyright notice by Blog Copyright